Lecturer's Précis -
Dennett (1978)
"Toward a
Cognitive Theory of Consciousness"
[Being Chapter 9 of
"Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology"]
Copyright Notice: This material was
written and published in Wales by Derek J. Smith (Chartered Engineer). It forms
part of a multifile e-learning resource, and subject only to acknowledging
Derek J. Smith's rights under international copyright law to be identified as
author may be freely downloaded and printed off in single complete copies
solely for the purposes of private study and/or review. Commercial exploitation
rights are reserved. The remote hyperlinks have been selected for the academic
appropriacy of their contents; they were free of offensive and litigious
content when selected, and will be periodically checked to have remained so. Copyright © 2018, Derek J. Smith.
|
First published online 12:00 BST 27th April 2007,
Copyright Derek J. Smith (Chartered Engineer). This
version [2.1 - link to graphic] dated 09:00 BST 3rd July 2018
1 - Introduction
Daniel C. Dennett [homepage]
[click for external
biography] is a professor of philosophy at Tufts University, and proposed
the architecture in question in Chapter 9 of "Brainstorms" (Dennett,
1978), as part of a broader discussion of the internal organisation
of the mind. It achieves three important things simultaneously. As a statement
on cognitive architecture, the model he puts forward is a good example of a
late-20th century A-shaped control hierarchy [for an introduction to which, see
Section 2.1 of the companion resource on "Human Error"].
As a statement on mental philosophy it shows how much of the mind's organisation can be accounted for without running up
against the age-old problems of phenomenal
consciousness [Glossary]
and subjectivity [Glossary].
As a mini-theory of speech production it shows how speech acts [Glossary]
are progressively converted into communicable language.
2 - The Model
Dennett was concerned to identify
the limitations of "functionalist theories" of the mind, that is to
say, theories which emphasise what is being processed
rather than how individual neurons might be cleverly clumping together to do
that processing. He is happy to describe himself as a "functionalist"
(p152), but confesses that the best available functionalist models only provide
a "sub-personal" interpretation. Here is his point in full .....
"Sub-personal theories proceed by analysing
a person into an organisation of subsystems (organs,
routines, nerves, faculties, components - even atoms)
and attempting to explain the behaviour of the whole
person as the outcome of the interaction of these subsystems. [..... They] characterise relations not between a person and a body, or
a person and a state of affairs, or a person and anything at all, but rather,
at best, relations between parts of
persons (or their bodies) and other things" (op. cit., p153).
He then drew the following flow diagram
showing how he saw these subsystems (a) being organised,
and (b) interacting within the resulting organisation .....
Figure 1 - Dennett's (1978) "Sub-Personal F Dennett's original]. The Control module [top, yellow] is responsible for the mind's
traditional higher function. It has
"executive" access to M, and can "introspect" into its
contents by using flowlines "Q" and "A". The Control
module also initiates requests (using the "speech act commands"
shown) for PR to produce speech [Garrett (1990)
provides a more detailed explanation of how the subsystems of speech
production interact, if interested].low Chart": Here are
Dennett's proposals for a "cognitivistic model
that by being sub-personal 'evades' the question of personal
consciousness" (op. cit.,
p154). Note the basic A-shaped structure [compare Lichtheim
(1885), Craik
(1945), Frank
(1963), and Norman
(1990)]. The Perceptual Analysis
leg [lower left, blue] is responsible for processing incoming information,
and in so doing makes use (a) of "a special short-term memory store or
buffer memory" called M, and (b) a "problem-solving
component". The PR Leg [lower
right, mauve] is responsible for the production of speech to match the speech
act sent to it [Dennett got the name "PR" from the
"print-out" routines commonly seen in computing systems in the
1970s]. It, too, has access to M [although the flowlines were omitted from
the original]. If this diagram fails to load
automatically, it may be accessed separately at |
Redrawn from Dennett (1978, p155; Figure 9-1), but with additional colour coding. This graphic Copyright © 2007, Derek J. Smith. |
3 - The Author's
Conclusions
Dennett assesses the value of his
diagram under two main headings. Firstly he points out that it reflects what is
known (or can with reasonable certainty be guessed at) about the subsystems of
cognition, as follows .....
"Psychologists faced with the practical
impossibility of answering the empirical questions of psychology by brute inspection (how does the human nervous system accomplish perception
or cognition) very reasonably ask themselves an easier preliminary
question: how could any (physical or
mechanical or biological) system accomplish perception or cognition? This
question is easier because it is 'less empirical'; it is an engineering
question, a quest for a solution (any solution) rather than a discovery" (op. cit., p161).
More importantly, though, the model
also helps identify those points within the cognitive architecture where the
subsystems are not enough, that is to say, where its sub-personal abilities need to be supplemented by something more
powerful. He has no final answers here, but dwells on our capacity for
unconscious registration of incoming information and the curiosities of our
"fringe consciousness".
4 - Evaluation
Here are some points which might
reasonably be made about Dennett's model, in revision point format
.....
5 - References
See the
Master References List
[Home]