Selfhood and
Consciousness: A Non-Philosopher's Guide to Epistemology, Noemics,
and Semiotics (and Other Important Things Besides)
[Entries Beginning with "J/K/L"]
Copyright Notice: This material was written
and published in Wales by Derek J. Smith (Chartered Engineer). It forms part of
a multifile e-learning resource, and subject only to acknowledging Derek J.
Smith's rights under international copyright law to be identified as author may
be freely downloaded and printed off in single complete copies solely for the
purposes of private study and/or review. Commercial exploitation rights are
reserved. The remote hyperlinks have been selected for the academic appropriacy
of their contents; they were free of offensive and litigious content when
selected, and will be periodically checked to have remained so. Copyright © 2006-2018, Derek J. Smith.
|
First published online 13:00 GMT 28th February 2006,
Copyright Derek J. Smith (Chartered Engineer). This
version [2.0 - copyright] 09:00 BST 5th July 2018.
BUT UNDER CONSTANT EXTENSION AND CORRECTION, SO CHECK AGAIN SOON
G.3 - The
Glossary Proper (Entries J to L)
Jackson-Meynert / Jacksonian
Model: See Hughlings Jackson, John and Meynert,
Theodor Hermann.
Jacquard,
Joseph: [French weaver (1752-1834).]
[Click for
external biography] See materialism
and underlying mechanism.
James, William:
[American philosopher-psychologist (1842-1910).] [Click for external biography].
See consciousness, James' theory of
and the entry for the James-Lange theory
of the emotions.
James-Lange Theory: This is the name given to the particular
theoretical position as to the relationship between overt behaviour and the
experience of the emotions, which holds that we feel the emotion after
the behaviour has been instinctively triggered, and not that we feel the
emotion first and then behave in accordance with that feeling. The
interpretation was published independently in Europe by Lange (1885) and in
America by James (1884), and we reproduce the core argument from the former in the entry for Lange, Carl Georg.
Janet, Pierre:
[French psychiatrist (1859-1947).] [Click for external biography]
See hysteria.
JAS: See Jenkins Activity Scale.
Jennifer: See case, Jennifer.
Jessie
Gilbert: See case, Jessie
Gilbert.
Job Execution Scheduling: [See firstly contention
scheduling.] Within computer science, this is the facility provided by
virtual machine mainframe operating systems for managing the "job
queue" - that is to say, the various demands on the machine's resources.
[See Section 1.2 of our e-paper on
"Short-Term Memory Subtypes in Computing and Artificial Intelligence"
(Part 5), for a longer introduction, if interested.]
Jones,
David: [Welsh artist-poet
(1895-1974).] [Click for
external biography] David Jones was the author, amongst other things, of
"In Parenthesis" (Jones, 1937, 1962), a first-hand account (thinly
disguised as fiction) of the assault during the Battle of the Somme by the 38th
(Welsh) Division on Mametz Wood, France, July 1916,
from which many did not return [see modern monument].
Jones is relevant in the present context as a fine exploration of the sort of
compulsions born of survivor syndrome.
[Compare Ancient
Mariner and Aneurin.]
Jones, Ernest:
[Welsh psychoanalyst (1879-1958).] [Click for external biography]
Jones is noteworthy in the context of the present glossary for his work as Freud's biographer.
Joseph Rowntree Foundation: This is the charitable body [corporate homepage] founded in 1904 by
the Quaker philanthropist Joseph Rowntree
to help counter the effects of social deprivation in Britain. It is noteworthy
in the context of the present glossary for its work on the problem of homelessness and other sequelae of toxic parenting.
Judgment: In
everyday usage, "judgment" is both a process and the outcome of that
process. As a process, it is "the formation of an opinion or notion
concerning something by exercising the mind upon it" (O.E.D.), whilst as
an outcome, it is the proposition by which that opinion is given
its communicability. [See now judgment,
analytic and judgment, synthetic.]
Judgment, Analytic: [See firstly a priori knowledge.] This is one of the two types of reasoning
identified by Kant (1781, 1787/1996) as capable of generating a priori
knowledge (the other being synthetic judgment). A judgment is to be
deemed both analytic and a priori,
if the proposition in question is inherently superficial, as would be the case,
for example, with "all bachelors are unmarried" (Kitcher,
1996, xxix), where the truth of the
predicate is already attributional to the subject. [Compare judgment, synthetic.]
Judgment,
Synthetic: [See firstly a priori knowledge.] This is one of the two types of reasoning
identified by Kant (1781, 1787/1996) as capable of generating a priori
knowledge (the other being analytic judgment). A judgment is to be
deemed both synthetic and a priori,
if the proposition in question might genuinely be informing you of something
you did not already know, as would be the case, for example, with "all the
monks are unmarried", where the truth of the predicate needs to be
established as a new attribute of the subject. [Compare judgment, analytic.]
Jung, Carl:
[Swiss psychoanalyst (1875-1961).] [Click for external biography]
Jung is noteworthy in the context of the present glossary for his distinctive
brand of psychodynamic theory. See
the entries for aggression,
psychodynamic theory and, alien
abduction, Myers-Briggs Type
Indicator, and Personification (1).
Kant, Immanuel:
[German philosopher (1724-1804).] [Click for external biography]
The best way to learn about Kant's right to a place in this glossary is to work
your way through all the entries beginning "transcendental .....", and their onwards links.
Karla: See case, Karla.
Kate: See case, Kate.
Kelly, George Alexander: [American psychologist (1905-1967).] [Click for
external biography] See personal
construct theory, perspectives,
humanistic, and aggression,
humanistic theory and.
Kernberg, Otto F.: [Austrian-born American psychotherapist (1928-).] [Click
for external biography] Kernberg is noteworthy in
the context of the present glossary for his work on borderline personality disorder and personality, splitting of.
Kierkegaard, Søren Aabye: [Danish theologian-philosopher (1813-1855).] [Click for external
biography] We mention Kierkegaard in the present context for his interest
in "the pathology of selfhood". Here is Hannay (1998) on this .....
"[Kierkegaard] thinks the sickness is
self-induced - not induced by itself, as could be said of any disease - but
induced by the people whose sickness it is. [.....] The morbid condition he
discerns is one we 'cause' just by wanting to be or to remain in it. [.....]
The sickness is called 'despair', and Kierkegaard calls it a sickness of the
spirit [.....] the fact that human beings are self-conscious. [..... It is] the
wish to be rid of oneself ....." (Hannay, 1998/2006
online).
Kinaesthesis: See
proprioception.
Kintsch, W.:
[American cognitive scientist (1932-)] [Homepage] See LTWM
and representation.
Klein, Melanie: [Austrian psychoanalyst (1882-1960).] [Click for external
biography] See Kleinian School.
Kleinian School: This is the name given to the followers of Melanie Klein's version of psychodynamic theory,
predicated as it was upon the insistence that aggression is indeed a primary
psychological drive [see under aggression,
psychodynamic theory and for the history of the debate on this issue].
Amongst those she influenced were
William Fairbairn, Donald Winnicott, Margaret Mahler, Edith Jacobsen, Otto Kernberg,
and Heinz Kohut. [See now object relations theory.]
Knowledge:
[See firstly epistemology.]
"Acquaintance with facts, range of information" (O.E.D.). The
Platonic view of knowledge was that it was the seeing or grasping of ideas within the mind (Hare and Russell, 1970, p22), which is not that far removed
from the modern view that knowledge is the sum total of the representations of
the world contained in a given mind, on all subjects (including our own
selves). The fact that there are different ways to encode the external world
means that a number of underlying memory types combine in different ways to
support a rich array of different knowledge
types. Knowledge thus becomes "an individual's utilization of
information and data complemented by his or her unarticulated expertise,
skills, competencies, ideas, intuitions, experience, and motivations"
(McQuay, 2005). However, if this term proves too general in technical
arguments, then use the more precise propositional
knowledge and procedural knowledge
instead.
Knowledge Economy: [See firstly knowledge.]
This term became popular in the 1990s to describe the growing systemic reliance
of the economies of the Western world on knowledge, either directly as a
marketable commodity, or indirectly as the key to competitive advantage in
conventional commerce. Although the term itself is only young, Mokyr (2002)
helpfully traces the notion of the economic value of knowledge all the way back
to the Greek myths, to Athena, the Goddess of Wisdom, and observes that procedural knowledge (which he names gamma knowledge) and propositional knowledge (which he names
omega knowledge) normally exist in a
stable equilibrium maintained by a negative feedback. We make the occasional
new invention, but in isolation its impact is not enough to change our way of
life. Our procedures, in other words,
do not substantively change our understanding
of the world. Every now and then, however, in the periods we know as Industrial
Revolutions, this feedback mechanism suddenly flips to provide positive
feedback, so that advances in procedural knowledge become part of that
understanding and generate demand for more of the same. [See now knowledge management.]
Knowledge Management: [See firstly knowledge
economy.] The applied (not to say blatantly commercialized) arm of
theoretical epistemology. The study
of the dynamics of individual knowledge in an organizational environment,
carried out with a view to securing corporate advantage. One of the support
industry skills of knowledge management is the sort of business analysis
carried out during information systems development, or, more specifically, the
sort of data analysis carried out during the logical design phase of a computer database. [See now wisdom.]
Knowledge Net: This is Kintsch's
(1998) synonym for propositional network, as the underlying mechanism of
mental representation.
Knowledge Types: [See firstly epistemology
and knowledge] A classificatory
breakdown of knowledge; an
epistemology. The point is that for all but the simplest of organisms, the very
act of existing involves the acquisition and use of knowledge. We need to know
how to hunt, how to feed, how to mate, how to fabricate, and how to
communicate. We need to recognize all the beings, places, and things in the
world, and we need to know for each whether it is good or bad to eat, whether
it is friend or foe, etc. When we get it right, we are comforted or sheltered
or rewarded in some way. When we get it wrong, however, we go hungry or cold. Or worse. Knowledge helps us face up to these problems and
make the decisions necessary to behave effectively. So what, then, is
knowledge? As recently as 1972, Karl Popper, in his influential book on the
philosophy of science, "Objective
Knowledge", stated that "knowledge consists of information
received through our senses" (Popper, 1972, p61). Here are some other
views: "Private Knowledge consists
of the events of consciousness. [] Common
Knowledge, for all practical purposes, is that part of private knowledge
that can be expressed by means of words. Propositions
are sentences which assert or deny something []. Facts are propositions which are true" (Burniston Brown, 1952, p43 - italics original);
"Knowledge is the name we give to conceptual structures built from and
tested against our own experiences of actuality" (Skemp,
1979, p30); "Knowing that, knowing
how, and being able to are
different, though closely connected" (Skemp,
1979, p167 - italics original); "Learning how or improving in ability is not like learning that or acquiring information"
(Ryle, 1963, p58 - italics original); "Declarative
knowledge refers to factual knowledge [and] often takes the form of a
series of related facts. [] procedural
knowledge refers to the knowledge underlying skillful
actions" (Best, 1992, p7 - italics added). One of the most critical
distinctions (see the quotations from Ryle, Skemp, and Best above) is the one between knowing that and knowing how.
Kohut, Heinz: [Austrian (later American) psychoanalyst
(1913-1981).] [Click for
external biography] Kohut is noteworthy in the
context of the present glossary for his work on the psychology of self.
Kopf: [German = "(fig.) brains, ability;
understanding, judgment, sense; memory; will" (C.G.D.).] See mind.
Kraepelin, Emil: [German psychiatrist (1856-1926).] [Click for external biography]
Kraepelin is noteworthy in the context of the present
glossary for his work on the cognitive impairments typically associated with
schizophrenia - see under cognitive
deficit for some of the details.
Kretschmer, Ernst: [German psychiatrist (1888-1964).] [Click for external
biography] Kretschmer is noteworthy in the context of the present
glossary for his contribution towards personality theory.
Krystal, John H.: [American clinical pharmacologist.] [Homepage] Krystal
is noteworthy in the context of the present glossary for his attempts at
filling in the explanatory gap between psychopharmacology and psychiatry. In
Krystal et al (2005), for example, he dicusses biochemistry in the light of psychoses and cognitive function.
Külpe, Oswald: [German philosopher (1862-1915).] [Click for external
biography] See Würzburg School.
KZ Syndrome: See survivor syndrome.
Label: See indexing.
Laing, Ronald David ("R.D."): [Scottish psychoanalyst (1927-1989).] [Click for external biography]
Laing is noteworthy in the context of the present glossary for his work on aggression,
hearing voices and and self, divided. He also provides a good
example of the humanistic perspective with his "existential
phenomenology", an approach to psychotherapy which he introduces as follows .....
"In existential phenomenology,
the existence in question may be one's own or that of the other. When the other
is a patient, existential phenomenology becomes the attempt to reconstruct the
patient's way of being himself in the world. [.....
N]o matter how circumscribed or diffuse the initial complaint may be, one knows
that the patient is bringing into the treatment situation, either intentionally
or unintentionally, his existence, his whole being-in-his-world" (Laing,
1960, p25).
Lange, Carl Georg: [Danish physiologist (1834-1900).] Carl Lange is most remembered
nowadays for his contribution to what went on to become famous as the James-Lange theory of the emotions. The
original publication was Om Sindsbevaegelser ("The Mechanism of the
Emotions") (Lange, 1885/1912), and the essence of the argument may be seen
in the following extract (a long passage, heavily abridged)
.....
"We have in every emotion as certain and manifest
factors: (1) a cause, -- a sense impression, which acts as a rule by the aid of
memory, or of an associated idea; -- and thereafter (2) an effect, namely, the
previously discussed vasomotor changes, and further, issuing from them, the
changes in the bodily and mental functions. The question now arises: What lies
between these two factors? Is there anything at all? If I begin to tremble
because I am threatened with a loaded pistol, does first a psychical process
occur in me, does terror arise, and is that what causes my trembling,
palpitation of the heart, and confusion of thought; or are these bodily
phenomena produced directly by the terrifying cause, so that the emotion
consists exclusively of the functional disturbances in my body? [.....] The
current opinion, as already remarked, amounts to the statement, that the
immediate effect of a process followed by an emotion is of a purely psychical
nature, (therefore, either the creation of a new mental force, or the
modification of a previous mental state). Furthermore, it affirms, that this
event in the soul is the actual emotion, the true joy, sorrow, etc.; whereas
the bodily phenomena are only subsidiary phenomena, which indeed are never
lacking, but are nevertheless in and of themselves
wholly unessential. [.....] If we cannot rely, therefore, in this question upon
the testimony of personal experience, because it is here incompetent, the
matter is thereby naturally not yet explained. If the hypothesis of psychical
emotions be not made necessary by subjective experience, it may nevertheless be
requisite if without it one cannot perhaps understand how the bodily
manifestations of the emotions come into existence. We have consequently first to investigate, whether the bodily
manifestations of the emotions can come into existence in purely bodily ways.
If that is the case, the necessity of the psychical hypothesis is thereby
removed. [.....] Where this happens in an individual, he becomes according to
circumstances, depressed or distracted, anxious or unrestrainedly merry,
embarrassed, etc. Everything is without apparent motive, and even though he is
conscious of having no reason whatever for his anger, his fear, or his joy.
Where is there any support here for the hypothesis of psychical emotion? (pp673-680).
Lange, Friedrich Albert: [German
neo-Kantian philosopher and political theorist (1828-1875).] Lange joined
the University of Bonn as lecturer in the mid-1850s, quickly specialising in
the history of the materialist philosophers. He saw deep flaws in the
materialist position, but was also far from impressed with Hegelian idealism
(regarding Hegel as little better
grounded in reality than the Schoolmen
of the middle ages). "What was needed was a
philosophical approach that would be compatible with the recent successes of
materialist explanations as deployed by the natural sciences
" (Hussain, 2005 online, §4). Now Lange was particularly impressed
by Helmholtz's work on the
experimental physiology of optics and acoustics, because this had brought hard
science and mental philosophy together in a way that Wundt and James would
shortly be capitalising upon in their respective laboratories of experimental
psychology. He therefore reworked Kantian theory to cope more effectively with
the available experimental data, publishing his ideas in Geschichte des Materialismus ("The
History of Materialism") (Lange, 1866/1925) a decade later. Helmholtz's
influential "Goethe address" (Helmholtz, 1953) was not forgotten, as
Hussain now explains .....
"Lange was one of the first in this period to
argue that the appropriate response to the philosophical situation in Germany at
the middle of the nineteenth century was to return to Kant. [.....] He sees
himself as agreeing with Helmholtz when Helmholtz 'resolves the activity of the
senses into a kind of inference' [Ref.]. It does not follow, he emphasises,
that 'the search for a physical mechanism of sensation, as of thought, [is]
superfluous or inadmissable. [.....] He concludes:
'The senses give us, as Helmholtz says, effects of things, not faithful pictures
let alone the things themselves. To these mere effects however belong also the
senses themselves, together with the brain and the supposed molecular movements
in it. We must therefore recognise the existence of a transcendent world order,
whether this depends on 'things-in-themselves', or whether [.....] it depends
on mere relations [Ref.]" (Hussain, 2005 online, §4).
In1872, Lange was appointed professor of philosophy at
Marburg University, where he corresponded for a while with the young Hermann Cohen [see separate entry]. His
insistence on at least a partly materialistic basis to cognition has led to his
system being described as "a psychology without a soul". He was also
an opponent of the method of introspection,
for the very reason set out in the Helmholtz extract above.
Lange, Karl:
[German Herbartian educational theorist (1849-1893).]
[No significant external biography available] In the present context, we note
Karl Lange as the author of Über Apperzeption ("On Apperception") (Lange, 1879/1889),
in which he reported practical studies on the best way to educate children.
Language Difficulties: See learning
disability and special educational need, the basics.
Language of Thought: This is Fodor's (1975) term for "mentalese", that is to say, the lingua franca of the mind's most abstract thought processes. In the
context of the present glossary, we may see it as an array of sememe
activations made linguistically coherent by the rules of some form of internal
grammar, and capable, moreover, of entering the speech production hierarchy at the "top" and thereby
being converted into appropriately surface utterance. This is a complex issue
within philology and psycholinguistics, but here is how one theorist has tried to
state the very nub of the problem (a long passage, heavily abridged) .....
"WHAT THE
PRIVATE LANGUAGE MUST BE LIKE: [.....] Where we
have gotten to is this: If learning a language is literally a matter of making
and confirming hypotheses about the truth conditions associated with its
predicates, then learning a language presupposes the ability to use expressions
coextensive with each of the elementary predicates of the language being
learned. But [.....] one can learn L
only if one already knows some language rich enough to express the extension of
any predicate of L. To put it
tendentiously, one can learn what the semantic properties of a term are only if
one already knows a language which contains a term having the same semantic
properties" (Fodor, 1975, p80).
[Compare the Richens-Booth continuous form interlingua
and Frege's
notion of the Begriffsschrift.]
Language of Thought Hypothesis (LOTH): See language
of thought.
Lanius, Ruth A.: [Canadian psychiatrist.]
[No suitable homepage] Lanius is noteworthy in the
context of the present glossary for her work on functional connectivity and dissociation.
Lateral Connectivity: The layered microstructure
of the cerebral cortex was first noted by Gennari in
1776 and Baillarger in 1840, and then analysed in
greater detail by Brodmann (1909) and von Economo (1929) [see the separate
e-resource on this, noting how Layers I, IV, and V are horizontal dendrite
layers]. [For a state-of-the-art application of the notion, see the entry for functional
connectivity.]
Law
of Closure: See closure, Gestalt Law of.
Law
of Common Fate: See common fate, Gestalt Law of.
Law of Continuity: See continuity, Gestalt Law of.
Law
of Proximity: See proximity, Gestalt Law of.
Law of
Similarity: See similarity, Gestalt Law of.
Laycock, Thomas: [British neurologist (1812-1876).] [Click for external
biography] See Hughlings Jackson.
LD: See learning disability and special educational
need, the basics.
Learned Helplessness: This is Seligman's (1975)
term for a generalised failure to engage with life's problems and challenges
consequent upon prior experience of failure. Seligman and Maier (1967)
originally noted the phenomenon while studying conditioning in dogs.
Using a "yoked pairs" paradigm, they exposed two dogs at a time to an
electric shock, but gave only one of the two dogs control over a conditionable avoidance response. With "normal"
dogs, the pattern was that the innate capacity for both the classical and
operant forms of conditioning soon shaped behaviour so as to avoid noxious
events. However, if the power to benefit from experience was somehow taken away
from the animal, its inability subsequently to learn to avoid a non-random
[i.e., predictable] shock diminished relative to a control animal. It had
learned not only that life was painful, but - and this was far more
debilitating - it had
learned that there was nothing it could do about it. The pain was now "noncontingent" upon any stimulus, and so commanded no
reinforcing power. It was not long before this animal conditioning paradigm got
adopted by human developmental psychology. In one of the early studies, Hiroto (1974) used loud noise as the noxious stimulus, and
found that human subjects who were taught the noncontingency
of avoidance in the experimental environment subsequently produced less
avoidance behaviour elsewhere. During the 1980s, an impressive body of
literature on learned helplessness in humans grew up (e.g. Cullen and Boersma, 1982; Berger, 1983; Stipek, 1988). This research
was prompted by the strong suspicion that the learned helplessness phenomenon
might actually be a key contributing factor to human unhappiness in general and
mental illness - not least depression - in particular. One of Seligman's
explanatory notions in this respect was that of "explanatory style" -
what mattered, in fact, was not the learned noncontingency
in itself, but how you rationalised that fact to yourself. It was
"perceived noncontingency" which was
debilitating in humans, and, although difficult to assess, in animals as well.
Learner's
Role: The
efficient transfer of knowledge between minds can only take place when the
communication channel in question is "open" at both ends. Learners
need to have committed themselves psychologically to what is about to arrive,
and engaged with a suitable knowledge source (be it a tutor, a peer, a parent,
a book, the Internet, a TV documentary, or whatever). The term "learner's
role" encompasses said state of mind. Gross (1997/2006 online) explains it this way .....
"The child defines himself as a
learner through various means, including: (1) how he experiences himself at
mastering skills and absorbing information; (2) how others see him and let him
know about himself and, (3) how he compares himself to others in terms of
mastering a new skill, (e.g., a sibling or peer may be reading while he is just
learning the alphabet; the kid down the block is good at ball, while he can
barely play 'catch'). The development of a sense of self as a learner starts in
very early childhood. Recent research has shown that children, prior to first
grade, are already making distinctions about how competent they perceive
themselves to be in different learning activities (including math, reading,
playing a musical instrument, and sports activities). As they get older, they
are increasingly adept at making distinctions about their abilities within
broader domains."
And again
.....
"As part of a child's
psychological development, there appears to be a mandate to create a coherent
self-concept as a learner. It becomes easy to see why a child with learning
disabilities can become confused and discouraged. A child with learning
disabilities has to assimilate contradictory information about himself as a
learner; e.g, 'I'm good at designing models, but I'm
slow in reading.' It is easy to see how a child with widely uneven cognitive
functioning could become overwhelmed and decide that he's a bad learner and
'why bother!' In such a case, the child's internal view of himself as a learner
can result in crippling feelings of hopelessness and failure. One of the biggest psychological challenges for such a
child is to develop an accurate self-concept as a learner which takes into
account both positive and negative learning experiences. How well a child
succeeds at this complicated task depends to a large extent on sustained
support and feedback from others early on as well as an ability to integrate
what he understands about himself in various learning situations."
[Compare academic locus
of control.]
Learning Difficulty: See learning disability and special educational
need, the basics.
Learning Disabilities "Tsar": At the time of going to
press (July 2006), this was a senior official at the UK Department of Health,
working alongside the National Director for Learning Disabilities, and
answerable to the Minister for Care Services. The first incumbent of this post
was Nicola Smith, previously at MENCAP. [see Department
of Health press release.]
Learning Disability (LD): See learning disability and special educational
need, the basics.
Learning
Disability, Cognitive Science of: There
has always been a two-way flow of benefit between those who deal hands-on with
a disability in the field, and the theoreticians and philosophers who merely
talk in abstract terms about that disability at academic conferences. In one
direction, we have clinicians and practitioners providing theoreticians with one
of their main streams of data, namely case reports. Theoreticians then relate
those data to the available formal theories of the mind, testing them, and
improving them when necessary. In the other direction, it is not unknown for
the theories - the cutting edge of cognitive scientific thinking - to be used
to generate new therapies .....
ASIDE: For an example of the interplay of a clinical
practicum and a theoretical model, we need look no further than the formative
years of the psychoanalytic movement. It was case histories of the effects of
hypnosis and free association which prompted Freud's initial conceptualisation
of the psychosexual world, but it was peer-review of the theory which fed back
into the enhanced clinical techniques used by post-Freudians such as Rank, Lacan, and Winnicott.
[See also learning disability, grieving and and learning disability, depression and.]
Learning
Disability, Grieving and: [See
firstly grieving process.]
Rothenberg (2006
online) has studied the grieving process in adults with learning
disabilities, and warns us that learning disability needs to be understood as a
loss to be grieved after. The dynamics of denial in bereavement, for example,
are fundamentally the same as the dynamics of denial in disability. Consider .....
"By
understanding one's limitations, an individual can discover how to compensate,
achieve and celebrate his or her unique learning style. If someone can not accept that he has these difficulties, then he may
be in denial. This can result in self-loathing and a tendency to compare
oneself to others. If the person is struggling with learning and sees that
others approach these same tasks with ease, he is going to have a negative
self-concept. He may begin to think that he is "stupid," which may
lead to low self-esteem, failure to try and further feelings of failure. A
negative spiral of despair may result" (Rothenberg, 2006
online).
Similarly, in due course, with the anger and
depression stages .....
"Once the shock wears off, the individual with learning
disabilities may find that he is angry. He may think about times that he did
not receive the help he badly needed. He may think of people who might have
helped, but for whatever reason, did not. He may feel 'robbed' of the support
that he might have had if others had recognized his problems earlier. An
individual may feel enraged because others have misinterpreted his difficulties
as laziness or emotional problems. When it is determined that there is a real
neurological reason for the difficulties, he may, for the first time, feel
entitled to his anger. There also can be self-directed anger because he did not
acknowledge his learning problems sooner. There can be rage directed towards
whatever or whomever he thinks may be responsible for the learning disabilities
in the first place - a feeling of 'Why me?' Just as it is critical to address
feelings of denial so that the process or mourning can begin, it also is
important to address the anger so that it does not become a crippling force. If
an individual with a learning disability becomes enmeshed with blaming or
self-pity, he robs himself of the possibility of moving forward. Once the rage
is addressed, he is often left with a feeling of profound sadness. [.....] It is a difficult loss to realize the
loss of the idealized self -- the self that was supposed to be. We all have
dreams and images of ourselves as we develop emotionally and cognitively that
can help, in a constructive manner, to drive us toward various goals. Having to
give up certain images of the self and dreams that we have had in order to
bring them more in line with reality is something that everyone faces as they
become adults. An adult with a learning disability often will be faced with
limitations that others may not experience" (Rothenberg, 2006
online).
Smith (1991, p186) movingly describes all this as
grieving "for what could have been". [See also masking.]
Learning
Disability and Special Educational Need, the Basics: [See firstly disabilityand mental
health.] Although the terms "learning disability" and
"special educational need" tell you at a glance what they are broadly
about the clarity ends there, for they are nowhere near as synonymous as they
look. A physical disability, for example, will count as an SEN under UK law if
it impairs either (a) mobility around an educational establishment, or (b) the
ability to engage with the visual and auditory material on offer, but it is not
itself a learning disability. It is also possible to have a special
educational need for language remediation or AD/HD management, even though
neither of these is, strictly speaking, a learning disability either.
The charity MENCAP list cerebral palsy,
epilepsy, autism, and Asperger's
disorder as learning disabilities
[check
it out], and mention Down syndrome and Fragile X syndrome as possible
underlying causes. The ICD-10 separates "mental retardation" from
"disorders of psychological development" and "behavioural and
emotional disorders with onset usually occurring in childhood and adolescence".
The Foundation
for People with Learning Disabilities lists AD/HD, Angelman's
syndrome [check
it out], autistic
spectrum disorders, and Down syndrome. Queens University, Belfast, lists
dyslexia, dyspraxia, dyscalculia, and Asperger's disorder as examples of
specific learning difficulties which might attract additional support resources
in university education [check
it out]. So in short it's a bit of a dog's breakfast. Here are the main
categories to consider, each one showing in parenthesis the Internet hit-rate
(mid-July 2006, UK pages only) and giving onward links if and when appropriate .....
Clumsy Child
Syndrome:
[252 hits] See developmental dyspraxia (below).
Developmental
Dyscalculia: [221 hits] This is the technical term for numeracy problems as they
afflict the general child population and as they manifest themselves in
everyday education as a specific
learning difficulty (below). For a detailed introduction to the symptoms
and main theories of developmental dyscalculia, see Sections 4 and 6 of our e-resource on
"Mathematical Cognition".
Developmental
Dyslexia: [21,700 hits] This is dyslexia as it afflicts the general child population
and as it manifests itself in everyday education as a specific learning difficulty (below). For a detailed introduction
to the symptoms and main theories of developmental dyslexia, see Section 4 of
our e-resource on
"Dyslexia".
Developmental Dyspraxia: [956 hits] [US = "developmental coordination
disorder"] Usually referred to in the vernacular
as "clumsy child syndrome", developmental
dyspraxia reflects a failure on the part of the motor hierarchy to develop smooth control over the skeleto-muscular resources at its disposal. As a result,
the processes of selecting a motor schema for execution, initiating it, and
then seeing it through to completion, are jerky and uncoordinated. It is
apparent from inspection of the motor
hierarchy that there are a number of potential fail points in the control
system. Moreover, since the most likely physiological root cause seems to be a
quite diffuse neuronal immaturity, the motor deficits tend to co-occur with
other types of pathology, such as lack of imaginative play, learning
difficulties, poor concentration, literacy problems, and relationship problems.
Dyscalculia:
[72,800 hits] Avoid this term since it fails to distinguish between the
acquired and the developmental variants of the disorder. See instead developmental
dyscalculia.
Dyslexia: [3
million hits] Avoid this term since it fails to distinguish between the
acquired and the developmental variants of the disorder. See instead developmental
dyslexia.
Dyspraxia:
[261,000 hits] Avoid this term since it fails to distinguish between the
acquired and the developmental variants of the disorder. See instead developmental
dyspraxia.
General Learning
Disability: [13,800 hits] A child with general learning disability has a
learning disability across
the spectrum of educational domains [compare specific learning difficulty (below), where the deficit is
restricted to just one domain, such as literacy]. Communication and
comprehension are typically both affected, and since critical comparison with
the "normal" population is inevitable, the child's self-esteem
suffers accordingly.
Language
Difficulties: [423,000 hits] Language difficulties are special educational needs, but
not strictly learning disabilities (because language is not learning in the
sense that one sits down in a classroom environment deliberately to do it). We
cover this topic under the entries for semantic-pragmatic disorder and specific
language impairment.
Learning
Difficulty: [281,000 hits, but will
pick up the 56,800 "specific learning difficulty" entries as well]
Children have a learning difficulty if they (a) have a "significantly
greater difficulty in learning than the majority of children of the same
age", and (b) "have a disability which prevents or hinders them from
making use of the educational facilities of a kind provided for children of the
same age". Learning difficulties are thus the defining factor in
establishing special educational needs.
Learning
Disability (LD): [2.3 million hits]
In UK practice, this term "used to be known as mental handicap or mental
retardation" (Royal College of Psychiatry website). It is roughly divisible
into two areas, namely "general learning disability" and
"specific learning difficulties", although, strictly speaking,
this leaves specific language disorders not properly accounted for.
PMLD: See profound and multiple learning difficulties
(below).
Profound and
Multiple Learning Difficulties (PMLD):
[165,000 hits] Applies to cases with at least two learning disabilities, severe
enough in total to exclude the child from mainstream education.
Special
Educational Need (SEN): [271,000
hits] Under this body of UK legislation and social provision, a child has an
SEN if the system says s/he has, and in making this judgment the system will
have assessed whether the child's failure to thrive educationally in the normal
school environment is "significant". This includes children with a
physical disability who accordingly find it difficult to access
educational provision, but would be quite capable of being educated by it if
they could gain that access. The problem with this state of affairs, of course,
is what happens to you if you come close to the trigger level but are then
judged not quite "bad enough" to qualify for the (not inexpensive)
package of benefits at stake. The answer here appears to be "not
much" [although we would be happy to accept correction on this].
Special
Need: [187,000 hits] In effect, and for the purposes of the present glossary,
special needs are the same thing as special
educational needs.
Specific Language Impairment: [34,000 hits] See the
separate main entry.
Specific Developmental Dyslexia: [40 hits] Perhaps the most common of the specific
learning difficulties. But avoid the term as such, because although it is
strictly correct the word "specific" repeats the superordinate
classifier, and the form "developmental
dyslexia" better reflects the fact that we are dealing with a
developmental rather than an acquired disorder.
Specific Dyslexia: [219 hits] Same as specific developmental dyslexia, and
same comments apply.
Specific
Learning Difficulty: [56,800 hits] This is probably the most popular term to describe problems
such as dyslexia and dyscalculia, where the deficit is
confined to one area of learning, leaving the child essentially normal in all
other respects. [Compare general
learning disability, where the deficit has to be "across the
board".]
Specific
Learning Disability: [652 hits] Avoid
this term in favour of specific learning
difficulty.
Specific
Learning Disorder: [39 hits] Avoid this term, because it is not underwritten by UK law or
professional practice and is rarely used academically. Use instead either learning disability, specific learning difficulty,
or special educational need as appropriate.
Learning
Disability, Depression and: [See
firstly learning disability and special
educational need, the basics.] Hollins
and Sinason (2000) get straight to the heart of this
particular problem .....
"An estimated 300,000
children and adults with severe learning disabilities live in the UK, and over
1,000,000 have a mild learning disability. The majority of
the latter live in relative poverty []. Many people have coexisting
physical disabilities and, not surprisingly given the burden they carry, there
is an increase in emotional disturbance in proportion to the severity of the
learning disability"
Hollins (2000) explains how
the psychiatry of learning disability is only some 25 years old. She outlines
how something as predictable as deaths in the learning disabled patient's
family used to go unremarked and untreated by clinical staff, even to the point
of leaving the patient out of the funeral arrangements! Bed and breakfast, yes;
but development of, and respect for, the person, apparently not. She
accordingly recommends involving the patient's family in case management, and
that, in turn, makes the entire parent-child dynamic relevant. On this point,
she stresses the role played by "the three secrets", thus .....
"All mothers bravely give birth knowing that their
child will die some day, but they usually assume it will be after
their own death, and that their child will, by then, be capable of
looking after him- or herself. But if the child is disabled, parental
fear of their own or their child's mortality may become an early preoccupation,
particularly if insecure attachment patterns have become
established. Denial of their own mortality may provide a more
comfortable way of coping with the extra dependency and
interdependency needs of their son or daughter, and may lead to no
plans being made for their child's own adult life. Is this why the
whole subject of death is such a painful secret where people with
learning disabilities are concerned? The denial of a person's
emotional life by parents and others may seem to be protective, but
should have no place in our professional care. A person with
learning disabilities will have similar emotional needs to other
people, but their expression of emotion may or may not be similar.
This will depend on whether they have found an acceptable form of
expression for their feelings. Sometimes the expression of a normal human
emotion may be dismissed as attention-seeking behaviour, or
described in different terms. For example, when my son loses his
temper, instead of having a short fuse, he has challenging behaviour.
There are two other secrets which are commonly kept from people with
learning disabilities: one is the secret of their sexuality, and the
other is the secret of their disability and dependency []. Ignorance of both of
these can lead to behavioural and relationship difficulties,
and both are probably contributory to the increased risk of abuse
faced by people with learning disabilities."
Learning Disability, Legal
Background to: In a professional
guidance report prepared in 2000, the British
Psychological Society cautioned against taking too narrow an approach to
learning disability. For example, the assessment of learning disability needs
to take into account "biological, psychological, and interactional factors,
within the broader social/cultural and environmental context" (BPS, 2000,
p2). The paper also states the three "core criteria" for a diagnosis
of learning disability as (1) "significant impairment of intellectual
processing", (2) "significant impairment of adaptive/social
functioning", and (3) "age of onset before adulthood" (p4). It
also appeals for a thorough understanding of psychometrics, since
psychometric tests are "the principle method" (p4) of assessing
levels of the intellectual processing component.
ASIDE: Psychometric instruments are not without their uses
in assessing the adaptive/social functioning component either. Readers who have
no background in psychometrics may pick up a smattering of the vocabulary by
spending a few minutes with the entries of validity
and reliability in our companion
glossary on "Research
Methods and Psychometrics".
The situation has been
coloured of late by legislation, notably the Disability Discrimination Act, 1995, the Special
Educational Needs and Disability Act, 2001, and the Mental Capacity Act, 2005. The government line is
therefore that "everyone with a learning disability can play a part in
making decisions about their lives" (HMSO, "Valuing People"). As
for children, the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child, 1989 states that disabled
children have the right to special care and training, and the right to have
their opinions taken into account in decisions made by others affecting them.
Indeed, the ability to runs one's own life is the key to promoting the selfhood
of the learning disabled child. For their part, the UK government recently
announced the creation of a "Learning Disabilities 'Tsar'" to advise
on how legislation and public services can be improved.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm: [German philosopher-engineer (1646-1716).] [Click for external
biography] See consciousness,
Leibniz's theory of, as well as the entries immediately following.
Leibniz-Bayle Debate: See
consciousness, Leibniz's theory of.
Leibniz's "Mill": [See firstly explanatory
gap.] This
is a thought experiment devised by Leibniz (1714) to help make the point that
even were it possible to see the parts of the brain in action we would actually
be none the wiser about how those parts served cognition
.....
"We are moreover
obliged to confess that perception and that which depends on it cannot
be explained mechanically, that is to say by figures and motions. Suppose
that there were a machine so constructed as to produce thought, feeling, and
perception, we could imagine it increased in size while retaining the same
proportions, so that one could enter as one might a mill. On going inside we
should only see the parts impinging upon one another; we should not see
anything which would explain a perception. The explanation of perception must
therefore be sought in a simple substance, and not in a compound or in a
machine" (Leibniz, 1714, Monadology, p5).
It is perhaps debatable
whether Leibniz would have held so strongly to this view in the light of the emergent
properties
debate, where the emphasis is on wholes invariably being greater than the sums
of their parts. On the other hand, he would have been reassured in his
scepticism by the fact that modern neuro-imaging techniques give us a
non-invasive means of seeing "the parts impinging upon one another",
but are nevertheless regularly at a loss to explain exactly what they are
looking at!
Leibniz's "Other" Mills: See the endnote to the entry
for minute
perceptions.
Leibniz's Two Clocks: This is a thought
experiment devised by Leibniz (1714) to help put across his rather
unique conceptualisation of soul .....
"Imagine two clocks
[which] always tell exactly the same time. This can be done in three
ways. The first is by the mutual influence of one clock on the other; the
second, by the attentions of a man who looks after them; the third, by their
own accuracy. The first way, that of influence, was discovered
experimentally to his great surprise by the late M. Huygens [detail]. The
second way of making two clocks (even poor ones) always tell the same time
would be to have them constantly looked after by a skilled workman, who adjusts
them from moment to moment. I call this the way of assistance. Finally, the
third way would be to make these two clocks, from the beginning, with such
skill and accuracy that we could be sure that they would always afterwards keep
time together. And this is the way of pre-established agreement. Now put the
soul and the body in the place of these two clocks. Their agreement or
sympathy can also come about in one of these three ways. The way of
influence is that of the commonly accepted philosophy; but as we cannot
conceive either material particles or species or immaterial qualities which can
pass from one of these substances into the other, we are obliged to reject this
view. The way of assistance is that of a system of occasional causes;
but I maintain that this is to bring a deus
ex machina into natural and everyday things. Thus
there remains only my theory, the way of pre-established harmony, set up
by a contrivance of divine foreknowledge, which formed each of these substances
from the outset in so perfect, so regular, and so exact a manner, that merely by
following out its own laws [.....] each substance is nevertheless in harmony
with the other, just as if there were a mutual influence between them
....." (p192; bold emphasis added so as to pick out the core argument).
It is perhaps debatable
whether Leibniz would have held so strongly to this view had he lived a hundred
years later, and seen, for example, Galvani's demonstration of the electrical
nature of the nerve impulse.
Leonie: See case, Leonie.
Les: See case, Les.
Lexicon: See
this entry in the companion Psycholinguistics
Glossary.
Libido: This
is the formal psychoanalytic name for the sort of energy which Freud (1895)
described in his Project for a Scientific
Psychology [see Freud's Project]. It is primarily generated
by the sexual instinct, and is capable of attaching itself to particular object
representations in the unconscious mind by the process known as cathexis.
Lichtheim's
"House": Lichtheim (1885) added to the then-raging localisation of function debate by presenting a set of explanatory
diagrams showing how the language centres (as he conceived them to be) were
connected up. These diagrams placed auditory memories and motor memories in
different centres (the "A" and "M" centres respectively),
thus: "We may call 'centre of auditory images' and 'centre of motor
images' respectively, the parts of the brain where these memories are
fixed" (Lichtheim, 1885, p435). A third concept
centre (the "B" centre - from the German word Begriffe) took care of
the associated semantic elements of the equation. The beauty of the resulting
diagram - affectionately known as "Lichtheim's house" - is that a different
aphasic syndrome naturally follows damage to any single pathway or any single
centre (compare Charcot above). Lichtheim was also
one of the first to recognise the diffuseness of higher-order cognitions (or
what we today term the "semantic system" or the "central
executive"). In his Figure 7, he placed these in a set of distributed
"conceptual centres".
Limbic
Irritability: See abuse-related brain damage.
Limbic System: See the companion resource.
Limbic System
Checklist (LSCL-33): [See firstly abuse-related brain damage.] This is a measure of limbic
system
irritability devised by Teicher, Glod,
Surrey, and Swett (1993). It consists of 33 rating scale questions, each
probing a behaviour suspected to be mediated by structures of the limbic
system. Among the areas screened for are "paroxysmal somatic
disturbances", "brief hallucinatory events", "visual phenomena",
"automatism", and dissociative experiences. Standardisation studies
have indicated that control subjects typically score below 10 on the scale,
whilst temporal lobe epileptics score over 23. Teicher
et al (2006) have described LSCL-33 scores as "dramatically
influenced" by abuse history, "more so than any other variable we
have examined" (p994).
Limiting
Membrane: This is Winnicott's (1960) term for the perceived surface of the
infant's physical self, that is to say, that which sets him/her off from the
world outside. Consider
.....
"The result of healthy progress in the infant's
development during this stage is that he attains to what might be called 'unit
status'. The infant becomes a person, an individual in his own right.
Associated with this attainment is the infant's psychosomatic existence, which
begins to take on a personal pattern; I have referred to this as the psyche
indwelling in the soma. The basis for this indwelling is a linkage of motor and
sensory and functional experiences with the infant's new state of being a
person. As a further development there comes into existence what might be
called a limiting membrane, which to some extent (in health) is equated with
the surface of the skin, and has a position between the infant's 'me' and his
'not-me'. So the infant comes to have an inside and an outside, and a
body-scheme. In this way meaning comes to the function of intake and output
[.....]. During the holding phases other processes are
initiated; the most important is the dawn of intelligence and the beginning of
a mind as something distinct from the psyche" (Winnicott,
1960, p589).
Lisa: See case, Lisa.
Litotes / Litotes: [See firstly figures
of speech.] [Greek = "plainness, simplicity" (O.C.G.D.).] This is
a habit of phrasal construction wherein an affirmative is deliberately
understated by an inbuilt negative, as in "no mean city" or "no
small tempest" (O.E.D.). As with all figures of speech, the principal
mystery is why the human cognitive system finds so little trouble coping with
the resulting construction, even when produced or heard for the first time.
Little Miss Muffett: This is Ryle's (1949, p63) thought experiment
and calls for the reciting of this well-known nursery rhyme backwards, while at the same time
introspecting how many separate acts of volition are involved. See the entry
for free will, Ryle's theory of for
details.
Liz: See case, Liz.
Lloyd Morgan's Canon: This is the name traditionally given to Lloyd Morgan's
(1894) caution that it is unwise to think of animals in anthropomorphic
(human-like) terms, attributing them with human emotions such as love,
gratitude, etc., simply because their eyes are bright or their tails are
wagging. Thus: "In no case may we interpret an action as the outcome of the
exercise of a higher psychical faculty, if it can be interpreted as the
exercise of one which stands lower on the psychological scale" (Op. cit., p53).
LNNB: See
Luria-Nebraska Neuropsychological Battery.
LoC: See locus of control.
Localisation of Function Debate: This is the name given to the academic debate which
has raged without interruption since the Napoleonic era, over whether brain
function is <localised, focal, and modular>, or <distributed, diffuse,
and systemic>. Readers may gain a feel for the general issues and the
specific confrontations by browsing as follows .....
(1) From our
Neuropsychology
Timeline: Check out the entries Gall, Flourens, Hughlings Jackson, Head, and Lashley.
(2) From our
Neuropsychology
Glossary: Check out the entries
for diagram makers and Globalist School.
As is
not infrequently the case with long-standing academic debates, the localisation
of function problem is actually a non-problem. What is really at issue is how
you interpreted the available data when you formed your personal position
opinion on the issue in the first place. Are you, for example, already a
committed Reductionist or Holist, and towards which psychological
"School" do you gravitate? The more you are an "-ist" of some sort, the more
likely you are to over-focus on the data which bear out your prejudices. In
fact, the brain is <localised, focal, and modular> and <distributed, diffuse, and systemic> according to where
you happen to be standing when you look at it, and how good your (metaphoric)
magnifying glass is.
Locke, John: [Class-defining British
Empiricist
philosopher (1632-1704).] [Click
for external biography] See the separate entries for abstract idea,
abstraction, idea, perception, primary quality, reality,
self, semiotics, and substance.
Locus of Control (LoC): This is the mental
dimension and fundamental personality factor proposed by Rotter (1966) to
reflect differences in how individuals perceive the causal relationship between
what they do mentally and what happens to them physically. Specifically, it is
a measure of where they stand on a scale running from "Other people [God,
fate, your boss, etc.] run my life" to "I run my own life". Here
is Rotter's original presentation of his ideas .....
"When a reinforcement
is perceived by the subject as following some action of his own but not being
entirely contingent upon his action, then, in our culture, it is typically
perceived as the result of luck, chance, fate, as under the control of powerful
others, or as unpredictable [.....]. When the event is interpreted in this way
by an individual, we have labelled this a belief in external control. If
the person perceives that the event is contingent upon his own behaviour or his
own relatively permanent characteristics, we have termed this a belief in internal
control. It is hypothesised that this variable is of major significance in
understanding the nature of learning processes in different kinds of learning
situations and also that consistent individual differences exist among
individuals in the degree to which they are likely to attribute personal
control to reward in the same situation" (Rotter, 1966, p1).
Later research has found locus of control effects
across diverse behavioural domains, including healthcare (e.g., Steptoe and
Wardle, 2001) and education. People with an external locus will look to others
- "the system" - to help them give up smoking, for example, or study
hard. In the present context, we must also mention that locus of control
appears to be central to the issue of coping behaviours. [See now locus of
control, academic performance and or locus of control, sports performance and as desired.]
Locus of Control, Academic Performance and: [See firstly locus of
control.] Needing, as it does, to begin at an early age,
"schooling" (be it at "school", or elsewhere) can only ever
be a given experience. Young children are required to attend and to
behave, and are expected to participate without protest in the educational experience.
Whether they are listening to the teacher, doing a classroom activity, or being
allowed to play, everything is structured by the educational system, such as it
is. It is therefore important that, as the child grows older, it is offered
increasing opportunity to manage its own learning. In 21st century Britain this
expectation contributes a little to the primary and secondary educational
experience, but begins to "bite" only in the first year of the
university experience AND NOT ALL UNDERGRADUATES TAKE EQUALLY TO IT.
ASIDE: In the present author's experience, voluntary level
1 tutorials have an attendance rate of only around 30%, despite attendance
being very strongly correlated to examination success.
Morris and Carden (1981)
looked at the exam performance of US college students in a two-by-two design,
grouping by internal or external LOC on one axis and extraversion or
introversion on the other. They found that the external locus of control was
positively related to their subjects' Neuroticism but unrelated to their
Extraversion. They concluded as follows .....
"This study adds to the growing body of
literature which indicates that extraversion-introversion and external-internal
locus of control, despite their similar-sounding names, are independent
personality dimensions. [..... T]he major predictor of performance differences
was locus of control, with internal scorers making higher grades than external
scorers as expected [.....] external extraverts performed the worst of the four
groups. [.....] On the one hand, neuroticism scores are a good predictor of
situational test-anxiety reactions, both emotionality and worry, while locus of
control scores are not. On the other hand, locus of control
scores are a predictor of academic performance, while neuroticism scores
are not" (Morris and Carden, 1981, pp804-805).
To help formalise research in this area, Trice
(1985) produced a psychometric measure of these individual differences, known
as the Academic Locus of Control Scale [see separate entry for details]. This was followed
up with an 18-item variant of Rotter's original IE-scale, designed to measure
students' approach to career development issues (Trice, Haire,
and Elliott, 1989). The authors called this latter measure the Career Development Locus of Control Scale (CDLC) and found that it
could closely predict which of a class of students approaching graduation had
so far done little in terms of sorting out their future employment. Here are
four out of the 18 questions, two indicating externality and two indicating
internality. .....
Q1. Getting a good job is primarily a matter of
being in the right place at the right time [true = external]
Q9. I expect to be hired for my first job on the
basis of the skills I have worked on developing [false = external]
Q10. One day I will just happen onto a career option
that is right for me [true = external]
Q17. I have only a vague idea of what I want to be
doing five years after graduation [false = external]
TEST YOURSELF NOW: Students wishing to specialise in
educational science should try generating half a dozen additional test items of
their own, and then checking against the full original to see how close they
were. THEY SHOULD THEN SCORE THEMSELVES AND REFLECT UPON WHAT THAT SCORE
REVEALS.
Locus of Control, Sports Performance and: [See firstly locus of
control.] ENTRY TO FOLLOW.
Logic (of a
Process): This phrase refers to the sequence of events by which a problem can be
solved. These events can be, for example, movements of, manipulations of, or
tests of, memory content. [Now see logic
circuit.]
Logic
Circuit: This is the name given to the functional components at the heart of
electronic computers, and their task in life is to manipulate one string
of binary impulses according to the content of another string of binary
impulses. Binary input is thus "processed" in a predetermined and
orderly fashion to produce binary output. In the Control Unit, this binary
input is the op code, and the
corresponding binary outputs are the electronic signals necessary to activate
the Arithmetic/Logic Unit. In the
Arithmetic/Logic Unit, the inputs are the control signals coming out of the
Control Unit, plus any relevant operands, and the output is the required
arithmetical result in the required memory location. Logic circuits were
originally invented by the likes of Charles Wynn-Williams, Konrad Zuse, George Stibitz, and John Atanasoff,
and their basic physical components are called "logic gates". Lewin (1985) describes logic
circuits as "combinational networks",
and summarises their operating principles as follows .....
"A combinational
logic circuit is one in which the output (or outputs) obtained from the
circuit is solely dependant on the present state
of the inputs. [] The classical objective of combinational design is to
produce a circuit having the required switching characteristics but utilising
the minimum number of components [] Switching problems are usually presented to
the designer [] specifying the logical behaviour of the circuit. From this
specification a mathematical statement of the problem can be formulated [and]
simplified where possible. These simplified equations may then be directly
related to a hardware diagram ....." (Lewin, 1985,
pp53-54.)
The speed of a logic circuit is usually measured in "instructions per second"
(nowadays, millions of instructions per second, or "mips"),
and this is determined in turn by the "clock
rate" of the system.
Logic Gates: Logic gates are electronic switches capable of
executing Boolean decision making, that is to say, combinatory binary symbolic
logic of the form developed in the nineteenth century by George Boole and Augustus de Morgan.
Logical Database Design: This is the first of the two basic phases in the
development of a database [the later
phase being physical database design].
It includes all the activities already dealt with in the entry for data
analysis and normalisation, and concludes when the metadata contained in the data model is further customised for a particular physical implementation,
that is to say, on a given machine, under a given operating system and DBMS, for a given corporate customer,
and so on. [See now physical database
design.]
Logorrhoea: See
this entry in the companion Neuropsychology
Glossary.
Logismos: [Greek =
"reckoning, computation, arithmetic; consideration, thought, reasoning,
reflection; cause, conclusion, judgment; project; reason, insight" (O.C.G.D.);
"reasoning, discursive thought" (Peters).] See ideation.
Logos: [Greek = "saying [.....]; discourse [.....];
thought, reason" (O.C.G.D.); "speech, account, reason, definition,
rational faculty, proportion" (Peters); "rational speech" (Beare, p107); "account of" or "formula
for" (Lawson-Tancred, 1986, p117).] In his translator's introduction to
Aristotle's De Anima, Lawson-Tancred (1986) warns that logos is "the hardest single word for the
Aristotelian translator" (p117). In his view, the most important of the
possible face-value meanings of logos is discourse for the purpose of
definition, because that is an indicator of how well you understand
the thing you are defining. Here is his personal logos on logos .....
"For something to be substance in the
fullest sense, it must be the possible subject of a definition and thus of
fundamental knowledge, and it must thus constitute the logos of a particular
thing" (Lawson-Tancred, 1986, p63).
Long-Term
Memory (LTM): For the mainstream neurophilosophy of long-term memory, see this entry in the
companion Memory
Glossary. For various uses of LTM resources in the construction of the self and selfhood, or for the role which deficiencies in same might play in learning disabilities or mental health problems.
See also mental model and motor schema.
Long-Term Working
Memory (LTWM): [See firstly long-term memory
and working memory separately.] Ericsson and Kintsch
(1995) [useful
commentary and extracts] have recently introduced the concept of long-term
WM (an assertion which would once have been considered a contradiction in
terms) to account for tagging phenomena
in complex cognitive behaviours like the
comprehension of text. What Ericsson and Kintsch
noted was that such highly complex tasks typically require access to large
amounts of what is known as "domain specific" - ie.
logically themed - knowledge. You might see this, for
example, in having the rules fresh in your mind while playing a game of chess,
or your knowledge of memory theory fresh in your mind while reading this
paragraph. Ericsson and Kintsch therefore proposed
the need for matching domain-specific "retrieval structures" capable
of rapidly and flexibly retrieving information from LTM, and in some way of
pre-organising it to the demands of the problem.
These retrieval structures are then the mechanism by which ongoing thought can
turn to a particular domain of knowledge and immediately be served up with a
"control panel" of sorts, by which the LTM within that domain is best
handled. The fact that these retrieval structures were undeniably LTM
structures themselves, but could interface flexibly
with ongoing cognition, led to them being termed LTWM. For our own part, we see
LTWM as demanding precisely the sort of "touch-and-glow"
electrochemical medium-term memory promised by second messenger
neurotransmission.
Lordat, Jacques: [French army surgeon (1773-1870).] See the separate file.
LOTH: See language
of thought.
Lotze, Rudolf Hermann: [German philosopher (1817-1881).] [Click for external
biography] See objective
idealism.
LSCL-33: See
Limbic System Checklist.
LTM:
See long-term memory.
LTWM:
See under long-term working memory in the companion Memory Glossary.
Luria-Nebraska
Neuropsychological Battery (LNNB): [See firstly executive function and dysexecutive syndrome.] The LNNB is a
14-subscale battery of "unstructured qualitative" neuropsychological
tests [see sales material].
The full test takes around two and a half hours to complete (Anastasi, 1990),
and the final paperwork includes a "mountain range" graphic plot (or
"profile") of standardised T-score
performance on the 14 subscales.
Lysosome: This is a small
spherical organelle containing digestive enzymes. Lysosomes help
"sweep up" foreign substances entering the cell.
See the
Master References List
[Up]
[Home]