Selfhood and
Consciousness: A Non-Philosopher's Guide to Epistemology, Noemics, and
Semiotics (and Other Important Things Besides)
[Entries Beginning with "M/N/O"]
Copyright Notice: This material was written
and published in Wales by Derek J. Smith (Chartered Engineer). It forms part of
a multifile e-learning resource, and subject only to acknowledging Derek J.
Smith's rights under international copyright law to be identified as author may
be freely downloaded and printed off in single complete copies solely for the
purposes of private study and/or review. Commercial exploitation rights are
reserved. The remote hyperlinks have been selected for the academic appropriacy
of their contents; they were free of offensive and litigious content when
selected, and will be periodically checked to have remained so. Copyright © 2006-2018, Derek J. Smith.
|
First published online 13:00 GMT 28th February 2006,
Copyright Derek J. Smith (Chartered Engineer). This
version [2.0 - copyright] 09:00 BST 5th July 2018.
BUT UNDER CONSTANT EXTENSION AND CORRECTION, SO CHECK AGAIN SOON
G.3 - The
Glossary Proper (Entries M to O)
M: See case, M.
Mach
Band Illusion: See consciousness, Mach's theory of.
Mach,
Ernst: [Czech physicist (1838-1916).]
[Click for external biography]
Although best remembered for his achievements as a physicist, Mach contributed
significantly both to the philosophy of science and to the psychology of
perception. [See now consciousness,
Mach's theory of.]
Machine
Code: In everyday computer jargon,
"machine code" is a generic reference to machine instructions, perhaps a just an instruction or two,
meaningless in isolation, perhaps a more functionally discernible routine
within a program, perhaps a program in its entirety, or perhaps an entire suite
of related programs.
Machine
Consciousness: The idea that one can
make a machine which is conscious of the world has always been a major theme
within mental philosophy. The classical myths, for example, are full of
inanimate things coming to life [cf. animism],
and the ancient Greeks were avid builders of automata [see separate fact
sheet]. The modern age of speculation was ushered in by the
arch-materialist Thomas Hobbes
(1588-1679), whose cognitive science is presented in the opening chapters of
"Leviathan" (Hobbes, 1651/1914). This classic opens with a
materialist stand which earned its author the opprobrium of Puritan and
Catholic alike: "For seeing life is but a motion of limbs, the beginning
whereof is some principal part within; why may we not say that all Automata
(engines that move themselves by springs and wheels as doth a watch) have an
artificial life? For what is the heart but a spring; and the nerves, but so
many strings ....." (Hobbes,
1651/1914, p1).
ASIDE: Descartes said much the same - for examples see consciousness, Descartes' theory of. It
is also what the arch-mechanist Julien La
Mettrie had in mind when he gave "L'Homme Machine" the following
second subtitle: "The different states of the soul are shown to be
co-relative to those of the body" (La Mettrie, 1750, titles).
Coming right up to date, machine consciousness is
nowadays an application area within the broader science of artificial intelligence (AI). Amongst the sceptics, Selmer
Bringsjord doubts that machines will ever be that clever. In his book
"What Robots Can and Can't Be" (Bringsjord, 1992), he argues that the
Turing Test is pretty much a side
issue. He identifies a number of factors - principally free will -
"necessary for personhood" (p2). "Robots," he predicts,
"will get very flashy, [but] they'll never be people" (p6). McGinn
(1987) identifies two immediate problems: not only are there the traditional
difficulties defining consciousness, but we also need to be clear about what we
mean by "machine". He insists that a machine would need to be able to
think, feel, perceive, will, create, and imagine before we could class it as
lifelike, but that there is no theoretical barrier. "All
that is required," he argues, "is an intelligence of sufficient
ingenuity and know-how" (p281). Unfortunately, we do not yet know
what the critical property of the artefact might be, although "supervenience
assures us that the brain has some
property which confers consciousness upon it" (ibid.). McGinn concludes that you do not need to be biologically
alive in order to possess consciousness, but that it helps if your artefact has
to behave like a living thing "of a certain
sophistication" (p283). In other words, a conscious machine would need an embodied intelligence for without this
it would never be able to develop the necessary subjectivity (and subjectivity, note, includes the ability to
experience what it was like to be a
conscious machine). It would, in short, need a phenomenology of its own. More recently, Birnbacher (1995) has put
his finger neatly on the problem: when asked whether artificial consciousness
is possible, he suggests that we should reply that it all depends what you mean
by artificial and consciousness (p489).
Machine
Instruction:
In the context of computer science,
machine instructions tell the Control Unit
what to do. They consist (always) of a relatively short binary code known as an
"op code", usually
(but not invariably) followed by one or more binary codes to be used in the
resulting operation. The additional codes are called "operands", and may either (a) fully specify a data
value (a number or a letter-string, say) in an absolute sense, or else (b)
state the "address"
where that data value may be found elsewhere in the machine. The fully
specified data values are known as "immediate"
values, and the others as
"variables". The full repertoire of instructions available to
a given machine is known as its "instruction
set". Fodor puts this relationship rather neatly .....
"The critical property
of the machine language of computers is that its formulae can be paired
directly with the computationally relevant physical states of the machine in
such a fashion that the operations the machine performs respect the semantic
constraints on formulae in the machine code" (Fodor, 1975, p67).
Machine Translation
(MT): For a detailed history of this
application area, see Section 4.1 of the companion resource.
"Magic
Echo": Dennett's (1999)
delightfully poetic term for inner
speech.
Mahler, Margaret: [Hungarian (later American) psychoanalyst (1897-1985).] [Click for external biography]
Mahler is noteworthy in the context of
the present glossary for her work on separation-individuation and the often-underestimated deep
significance of its failures.
Main, Mary:
[American developmental psychologist (?).] [No convenient biography] Mary Main
is noteworthy in the context of the present glossary for her work on attachment and metacognitive monitoring therein.
Major Depressive Disorder: This is one of the three DSM-IV disorder groups under the category header of depressive disorders. It presents as a
sequence of major depressive episodes,
each of at least two weeks duration, characterised by extreme dysphoria
accompanied by a variable package of lesser indicators. The lesser signs
include catatonia, aggression, avoidance behaviour, unusual eating behaviour,
distractibility, hallucinations, impulsivity,
and memory impairment.
Major Depressive Episode: An episode of dysphoria,
clinically severe enough, and complete with enough secondary indicators, to
warrant consideration of a diagnosis of major
depressive disorder.
Malingering:
[See firstly differential diagnosis,
psychiatric.] Malingering in the everyday sense of the term is a clinical
sign used in the differential diagnosis of all disorders, both psychiatric and
medical. This is because the "feigning of symptoms" (First, Frances,
and Pincus, 1995, p172) needs to be carefully investigated whenever
"legal, financial, and other benefits [avoiding military service, perhaps
- Ed.]" (ibid.) might accrue from a misdiagnosis. Malingering
should not, however, be allowed to conceal the genuinely psychiatric factitious
disorders.
Malinowski,
Bronislaw Kasper: [Polish cultural
anthropologist (1884-1942).] [Click for external
biography] Malinoswki is noteworthy in the context of the present glossary for
his work on identity, comparative approaches to.
Managerial
Knowledge Units: [See firstly frontal lobe syndrome, planning, and script
execution.] This is Grafman's (1989) term for cognitive structures in the frontal
lobes which coordinate lesser blocks of memory into meaningful sequences [1994
press release]. It is more or less synonymous, therefore, with the terms action
schema and script. It has recently been described as a category of
script-like structures "with a beginning and an end and a hierarchical
organisation going from more abstract [.....] to more
concrete levels" (Chevignard et al, 2000/2003 online),
and highly susceptible to frontal lobe lesions.
Mania: [See firstly differential
diagnosis, psychiatric.] In everyday English, mania is "mental
derangement characterised by great excitement, extravagant delusions and
hallucinations, and, in its acute stage, by great violence" (O.E.D.). In
psychology the same basic definition applies, only there is then a much greater
emphasis on the role of mania in reflecting what might be going on at the
interface of our emotional and intellectual selves. As such, mania becomes both
the primary diagnostic variable for an entire cluster of mental health
disorders under the DSM-IV, and
a major source of theoretical insight to those interested in more philosophical
issues such as the mind-brain problem.
Clinically, mania and its companion construct hypomania are signs used in the differential diagnosis
of-and-within the various bipolar disorders.
The DSM-IV lists (p357) a number of important subfactors within mania, namely
that the patient's mood should be (a) elevated, (b) expansive, and (c)
irritable. There will also normally be inflated self-esteem verging on
grandiosity, a decreased need for sleep, and a certain "pressure of
speech" [cf. logorrhoea].
Manifest
Anxiety Scale (MAS): See anxiety, manifest.
Manifold: [See firstly figure-ground.]
In everyday English, the word "manifold" is most commonly seen as an
adjective meaning "varied or diverse in appearance, form, or character
[.....] numerous and varied; of many kinds or
varieties" (O.E.D.). Within mental philosophy, however, the word is used
as a derived noun, translating Kant's use of Mannigfaltige, to
refer to the many objects presenting
themselves in an external scene, the point being that the basic task of
perception is to make sense of such complexity. A manifold is thus
whatever is there to be analysed, in all its ontic granularity, each granule with
its own behavioural trajectory. [See now manifold, synthetic unity of.]
ASIDE: Metaphorically speaking, one can detect the problems
of the Kantian manifold in an Air Traffic Controller's radar screen. A modern
screen display enables many items, some moving, some not, to be tracked
separately against a stable perceptual background [Skyguide, the Swiss air
traffic people, have a specimen radar display available online - check
it out]. We have only to arrange for the background to be itself moving (as
would be the case if the installation in question were aboard an aircraft
carrier at sea), and we may simulate all the problems of life-like perception.
Manifold, Synthetic Unity of: [See firstly scene analysis in general, and manifold
in particular.] This is Kant's term for the quality of belonging
together of the separate items currently making up a given perceptual scene, thus .....
"What is first given to us is appearance. When
appearance is combined with conciousness, it is called perception. [.....] But
because every experience contains a manifold, so that different perceptions are
in themselves encountered in the mind sporadically and individually, these
perceptions need to be given a combination that in sense itself they cannot
have. Hence there is in us an active power to synthesise this manifold. This
power we call imagination; and the act that it performs directly on perceptions
I call apprehension" (Kant, Critique,
1781; Pluhar translation, pp167-168).
Mannigfaltige: [German = "various, manifold, diverse,
multifarious" (C.G.D.).] See manifold.
Mannikin Test: [See firstly executive function and dysexecutive
syndrome.] ENTRY TO FOLLOW
Many-To-One Relationship: See relationship,
many-to-one.
Marburg School:
This is the name given to a school of neo-Kantian
philosophers founded by Cohen at the
University of Marburg, Germany, in the 1870s, and
including in its numbers Cassirer
and Natorp.
Margaret: See multiple
personality disorder.
Marginal
Co-Data: This is Husserl's term for the
contents of the "outlying zone of apprehension" (Ideas, p125),
within which perception proper, as a focalising process [our term] takes place.
[See now the notion of database currency as a metaphoric mechanism of
"keeping tags on" these marginal contents.]
Marginal
Zone: See marginal co-data.
Marie: See case, Marie.
Marty,
Anton: [Swiss mental philosopher (1847-1914).]
[No suitable Internet biography available, but there is more than enough for
beginners in Smith (1994/2007
online)] Marty is noteworthy in the context of the present glossary for his
late-19th century work on what we know today as the theory of speech acts.
Mary Reynolds: See case, Mary Reynolds.
Mary's
Room: This is Jackson's (1982) thought experiment on the topic of qualia. Jackson asks you to imagine "color
scientist" Mary, who has learned everything there is to know about the
physiology of colour vision, but who has lived all her life in a
black-and-white environment full of black-and-white books and a black-and-white
TV. Participants in the thought experiment are then asked to judge what changes
in Mary's mind when finally she is allowed to leave the room and see colour for
herself for the first time. For his own part, Jackson believes she will
immediately learn something new, namely what
it is like to experience colours, and this, in turn, implies that there is
more to absolute knowledge than physical information could possibly provide. Dennett, on the other hand, challenges
the logical integrity of the argument. His view is that if Mary had not already
worked out what it was eventually going to be like seeing a colour, then she
could not properly be classed as knowing all there was to know about colour
science!
MAS: See anxiety, manifest.
Masking: [See firstly learning
disabilities.] In the context of learning disabilities, Smith (1991) warns
that clients often deploy a type of psychological defense mechanism known as "masking" in order to deflect
attention from their disabilities. Consider .....
"People with learning disabilities adopt these
masks to save what self-esteem they
can. The masks deflect attention from their disabilities and let them hide, or
avoid performing in, their weak areas. Such masks are destructive because they
allow people to avoid coming to terms with their learning disabilities"
(Smith, 1991, p43).
There seems to have been little research to date on
the similarities between masking as a defense mechanism and the whole issue of personae in the building of personality and self identity.
Mass Hysteria: See hysteria, epidemic.
Massive Modularity: [See firstly modularity.]
This is Sperber's (1994/2007
online) notion of a cognitive system built up from modules ranging in size from
large and specific cognitive domains (such as mathematical skill) at the top,
all the way down to individual concepts at the bottom. Here is the core
proposal [citations omitted] .....
"Taking for granted that domain-specific
dispositions are an important feature of human cognition, three questions
arise: (1) To what extent are these domain-specific dispositions based on truly
autonomous mental mechanisms or 'modules', as opposed to being domain-specific
articulations and deployments of more domain-general abilities? (2) What is the
degree of specialisation of these dispositions, or equivalently what is the
size of the relevant domains? Are we talking of very general domains such as
naive psychology and naive physics, or also of much more specialised dispositions
such as cheater-detection or fear of snakes? (3) Assuming that there are mental
modules, how much of the mind, and which aspects of it, are domain-specific and
modular? As a tentative answer to these three questions, I proposed in some
detail an extremist thesis, that of 'massive modularity'. [.....] I was arguing
that domain-specific abilities were subserved by genuine modules, that modules
came in all format and sizes, including micro-modules the size of a concept,
and that the mind was modular through and through" (Sperber, 1994).
Sperber offered this suggestion as a speculative
alternative to the then-predominant "Fodorian" approach, namely that
a relatively small array of "informationally encapsulated" modules is
coordinated by a single overarching higher-order (but non-modular) process.
Unfortunately, the term modularity permits so many interpretations that it is
difficult to make progress [Sperber notes no less than five "levels"
of analysis and discussion here]. Massive modularity has been a major topic of
debate ever since Sperber's paper, although the problems of definition continue
to cause problems. For example, Carruthers (2006/2007
online) has recently warned that there is no generally accepted
understanding of "what a massively modular model of the mind is", and notes both
"weak" and "strong" notions of what the word
"module" actually involves. The weak definition carries the sense of
mind component, but little more than
that. The strong definition, on the other hand, implies "a domain-specific
innately-specified processing system, with its own proprietary transducers, and delivering 'shallow'
(non-conceptual) outputs". Carruthers refers to strong modules as
"Fodor modules", because they possess the defining characteristics
originally suggested in Fodor's (1983) seminal paper on the subject.
ASIDE: Our own position on modularity has been shaped by our
experience as a database designer in the British computing industry in the
1980s, and is grounded on the observation that computers are and always have
been spatially (or "physically") distributed, even in the lowliest
system [readers unfamiliar with the terms "CPU", "registers",
"logic unit", or "bus" may care to glance at the companion resource
on the "general purpose" computer before proceeding]. This
physical distribution is then conflated with the functional distribution
to be seen in the serially stored sequences of machine instructions we know as
"computer programs" [readers unfamiliar with either the notion of a
program's "structure", or the "Jackson diagrams" by which
that structure is represented graphically, will find the Wikipedia entry on
"Jackson structured programming" gently informative - take me
there]. The early computer systems simply trickled each functionally
modular sequence of instructions one by one through the maze of structurally
modular electronics, and, given sufficient programming skill and serviceable
electronics, this double contrivance delivered usable output. Gradually,
however, the size and complexity of both types of architecture - the functional
and the structural - started to creep upwards, until by the late 1950s
the ability of programmers to cope with the functional side of things started
to fall behind the number crunching power of the circuitry available. One way
around this problem was to separate out the logical and the physical aspects of
the design. The logical designers looked at what needed to be done in principle, recording their findings
in a standard format, and then the physical designers concentrated on how to
"implement" what the logical designers had passed them. [The
cognitive scientist David Marr was making precisely the same point when he
emphasised the need for independent study of the "computational
principles" of an information processing system (Marr, 1982).]
UNFORTUNATELY, THE CROSS-MAPPING OF THE LOGICAL AND THE PHYSICAL HARDLY EVER
FOLLOWS A ONE-TO-ONE PATTERN, and it is this decidedly
inconvenient truth which accounts for most of the confusion noted by Carruthers
above. For example, Carruthers himself describes the separately purchasable
components of a modular hi-fi system as "dissociable functional
components", when that is exactly what they are not - they are
dissociable structural components first and foremost [in Carruthers'
hi-fi, for instance, the sound delivery system (a discrete function) would be
implemented in an array of many physical modules (cables, speakers, etc.)]. For
a longer discussion of how to integrate the logical and physical aspects of
system design, see the companion resource on "Data
Modelling".
Materialism:
[See firstly mind-brain debate.] [a.k.a. physicalism.]
"Materialism" is one of the two possible monist positions in the mind-brain debate (the other being Idealism), and is, in the eyes of some
commentators, "an absurdity" (Eccles, 1987, p293). Specifically, it
is the notion that the laws of the brain, once they have been finally and fully
established, will be able to explain not just the workings of the brain, but
those of the mind as well. Since such an explanation would do away with
the need for an immortal soul, Hamilton (1865) immediately points to the
theological impact implicit in this position, arguing that "[if]
intelligence is only a product of matter, only a reflex of organization, such a
doctrine [.....] would positively warrant the atheist
in denying [God's] existence" (Sir William Hamilton, p.p. Mansell and
Veitch, 1865, p31). It may reassure the devout, therefore, to learn that no
workable Materialist explanation has yet been devised, and that Materialism
remains just another matter of personal faith. However, since the nature of any
age's Materialist explanations must always be rooted in that age's grasp of the
laws of science as they know them (and in the metaphors inspired thereby), and
since those laws are themselves a moving target, it is best to review the topic
historically, and we do this in a separate entry entitled Materialism and
underlying mechanism.
Materialism and Underlying Mechanism:
"Then
began the true work of the magician. The head was fastened upon a pedestal of marble.
Clockwork was placed inside of it. Wires were attached to the tongue, the
eyeballs, and other parts of the image. These were carried to mysterious jars
of chemicals hidden away in a dark closet. Everything was
done with care, strictly according to the directions given in the
manuscript" (Baldwin, 1905/2007
online, p36).
[See firstly Materialism
and its onward link to the mind-brain
debate.] This entry presents the most important Materialist theories of the
mind set against the timeline of practical invention. The story begins
before Plato, but comes right up to date with modern research into robotics and
artificial consciousness. The content is organised into five broad historical
eras, as follows .....
§ § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § §
§ § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § §
§ § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § §
§ § § § § § § § § § § §
There follows a long item, whose
substantive point can only properly be appreciated from the far end. Please be
patient with it.
Basically, we want to get from this, to this, to this!
§ § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § §
§ § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § §
§ § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § § §
§ § § § § § § § § § § § §
1. Classical
Materialism: We have to thank the
Greek philosopher Anaximander (fl.
ca. 570 BCE) for the notion that there might be common laws of matter and life
(Wikipedia), and we have to thank Leucippus and Democritus for the Atomist
notion of some final microscopic unit of matter. However, those ideas alone did
not constitute a Materialist theory of the mind, because matter, thus
conceived, just sits there, waiting for our inherent animism to elevate it to the status of mental equal. It is
therefore no surprise that classical views of the relationship between body and
soul [see soul, tripartite] were
never overly concerned with the possibility that matter built soul, seeing it instead as merely giving something which
already existed somewhere to
reside. To see matter as the mechanism
of soul required, firstly, some prior notion of mechanism; some appreciation of
matter in motion .....
ASIDE: Readers unfamiliar with the terms Reductionism and explanatory
gap should read the dedicated entries thereon before proceeding, because
mechanisms routinely acquire emergent
properties, and emergent properties can be surprisingly difficult to
reconcile with what is known about their parts. When considering what makes a
good holistic explanation of a system, Sherwood (1966) relates how both
James Clerk Maxwell and Kenneth Craik
had an eye for that system's "particular go", that is to say, they
would try to explain in as few words as possible how the mechanism moved within
itself, given the nature of its parts, to perform its higher-order function.
Unfortunately, when it comes to the mind, this is precisely the sort of
explanation which, thanks largely to the problems of phenomenal awareness and subjectivity,
continues to elude us.
It follows that before we can judge how good a
particular Materialist theory of mind is, we need some historical feel for the
timeline of mechanical invention. We will then be able to judge the theory
against the natural metaphors for mind which
were available at the time. We start the ball rolling with the
tension-powered catapult [image
and specification], an invention attributed to Dionysus of Syracuse in about
360 BCE. This was the first of history's "siege engines", and we have
selected it because it represented a quantum leap in design complexity. Earlier
inventions had had few moving internal parts, but now, in addition to the main
structure of trunnion and throwing arm, there were tensioners, ratchets, a
torsion module, a trigger mechanism, and so on. In other words, the battle
catapult was a system with inner logic
and had parts which rated as subsystems in their own right, not as mere
components [for the formal distinction between system and subsystem, see
the companion glossary on "Systems
Theory"]. It is no coincidence, we submit, that the first workable
"Materialist" suggestions on the mind-brain problem came within years
of Dionysus' invention .....
MATERIALIST THEORY #1: The Greek notion of the tripartite soul is far from being a Materialist
theory of mind, but the treatment given to memory within the tripartite scheme
actually comes quite close to it. Plato's Theaetetus, for example,
offers us the metaphor of memory as a wax block into which our experiences are
impressed, and in which impressed form they are stored. Consider (a long
passage, heavily abridged) .....
"SOC[RATES]:
Now I want you to suppose, for the sake of argument, that we have in our souls
a block of wax [.....]. We make impressions upon this of everything we wish to
remember [.....]; we hold the wax under our perceptions and thoughts and take a
stamp from them, in the way in which we take the imprints of signet rings.
Whatever is impressed upon the wax we remember and know so long as the image
remains in the wax [.....]. In some men, the wax in
the soul is deep and abundant [.....]. Men with such souls learn easily"
(Plato, Theaetetus, §191c-e/§194d;
Levett translation, p67/p70).
The material, in other words, served a mental purpose, but was less than full
ideation. Ideation was something for the immaterial soul to take care of, as
indeed was volition. To move of your own accord was to be alive, and
this, Plato reasoned, could only be a property of the non-material.
Moving on a generation, one of Aristotle's claims to
fame was that he served as mentor for a time to a young Alexander the Great [details].
In hindsight, there is no little irony in this, for as Alexander began pushing
Greek imperial boundaries out across three continents, the focus of science and
philosophy moved with him, ending up on the other side of the Mediterranean, on
the Nile delta at Alexandria. The Academy which Plato had created in 387 BCE [details] lost
its reputation as the place to study
to "the Museum", the library set up to grace the new city.
Thereafter, if a subject was worth knowing you could study it at Alexandria,
under such luminaries as Ctesibius,
Erasistratus, Herophilus, and
Eratosthenes. One of the subjects on the Museum curriculum was the "design
technology" of its day, that is to say, the study of mechanism, especially
if that mechanism could be relied upon to attract the research funding of its
day. Mechanics therefore became the science of siege-engines, automatic doors,
garden statuary, and theatrical display. Anything, indeed,
that the ingenuity of the students could think of. As a result, it was
not long before there was born at Alexandria the craft of automaton-maker .....
ASIDE: Readers who have not already seen the entry for automata
should check it out before proceeding. We shall be dealing at some length with
this particular topic because automata are a major recurring theme in the
history of cognitive science, and it helps to know exactly why. The most famous
of the Greek automaton-makers were Ctesibius
(the Thomas Edison of his day, by all accounts), Philon of Byzantium
(who would have been at his productive peak around 250-240 BCE, and whose
writings describe artifacts he himself may have had a designer's hand in), and Heron
of Alexandria (who wrote some 300 years later, and ought therefore to be
regarded more as archivist-practitioner than originator).
Now the point about automata is that they have a very
specific allure. They initiate their own movement, and self-initiated movement is a
very compelling property for a species as keen as ours is to attribute
mentality to inanimate matter. Movement makes the illusions born of our
inherent animism very convincing. It
gives them an instant and enduring Dasein of their own. This, in
turn, makes automata a powerful weapon in the hands of anybody "with a
palpable design upon us" [this wonderful phrase is from George Steiner],
and nobody ever has a more palpable design upon us than the priesthood
.....
ASIDE: We need at this juncture to recall that there had
been a flourishing business in the sale of quasi-religious "favours"
in Egypt since the earliest Pharaonic dynasties some three millennia
previously, and a parallel tradition of oracular mysticism in Greece at sites
like Delphi. The explanation, we believe, is clear - the greater an
individual's fear of the unknown, the more that individual will pay for a belief system which tells him/her that
everything is going to be OK. Massive temples mean equally massive promises in
areas such as personal immortality, financial wellbeing, and sexual or military
prowess. The fact that the ruins of these temples still dominate the skylines
from Stonehenge to Karnak to this day, confirms the power of such
promises to command a truly massive investment. As to the precise rituals themselves, interested readers may care to
divert for a moment to the story of Alexander the Great's personal
consultation with the Oracle of Ammon at Siwa[h], a temple at a remote oasis
south-west of Alexandria. A number of Roman historians give brief but revealing
accounts of this visit [read
these accounts].
So it was very much in the priesthood's interest to
play upon the fear-factor in the human psyche, and that - candidly - meant
resorting to trickery and sleight of hand. Ritual works best when it is both
seductive and scary, and so those responsible for delivering it would
have needed as much chemistry as they could get their hands on, anything,
indeed, which phosphoresced, spontaneously combusted, sparked, bubbled, gave
off coloured smoke, and so on. The priests would also have been practical
phoneticians, experts at the physics of reeds and sounding boxes and resonance,
so that they could punctuate their ritual with all sorts of eery sound effects.
Heyl (1964) assures us that both the head of the Jackal God and the bust of
Re-Harmakhis had hidden speaking tubes leading to their mouths, and Spence
(1915) adds that "every roguery of priestcraft" was practised in
Egyptian temples.
2. Dark Age
and Early Renaissance Materialism: As
things turned out, it was the priest-magician caste who were responsible for
just about the only real area of scientific advance over the next thousand
years, namely the primitive branch of chemistry now referred to rather
dismissively as alchemy. Chemistry
was simultaneously science and magic in those days (it was the
"shock and awe" of the Arthurian Age, if you like), and the
alchemists were the inspiration for the now-popular image of the Magi as rather
inscrutable wise men, and of Myrddyn (Merlin) as the archetypal
special-relationship aide to kings and generals. In short, the better your
retort-and-crucible skills and the more ruthlessly you applied them, the
further you could climb the ladder of success, even to the very top, witness
Hildebrand (Pope Gregory VII, pontiff 1073-1085), with his alchemical penchant
for "shaking lightning out of his sleeve" [tell me this story].
ASIDE: We strongly recommend MIT historian Bruce Mazlish on
this subject. He has studied the interplay of humankind and its technology over
the millennia, and identifies a number of "discontinuities" - periods
of major reworkings of our understanding of ourselves and our world. The
"hermetic tradition" underlying Western science was one of only four
such discontinuities ever, and alchemy was "the Hermetic tradition
par excellence" (Mazlish, 1993) [buy
this book]. Hellemans and Bunch's (1988) Timetables of Science
provides some pointers on when the change really kicked in. Their timelines of
astronomical, medical, and physical discoveries show that Arabian and Chinese
advances for the 9th to the 12th centuries, inclusive, outnumbered European by
about four-to-one. The Europeans then pulled themselves up to level-pegging
during the 13th century, and by the 14th century had turned the four-to-one ratio
round into their favour! As to why this might be, see Section 2.3 of our "Education
Timeline", and note how many Western European universities came on
stream in the 13th century! It is also worth briefly reviewing what sort of
non-chemical inventions were appearing in Europe and the by-now-Muslim Near
East around this time, especially those where improved wood- or metal-working
skills were allowing smaller, more internally sophisticated, end-products. Here
are some illustrative dates [for reasons which will eventually become apparent,
the inclusion of a number of musical instruments and clockwork devices is far
from coincidental] .....
Ninth
Century: The crank winding handle (earlier
in the Far East); the hot stone smoothing "iron".
Tenth
Century: The pocket sundial;
distillation of alcohol.
Eleventh
Century: The crossbow (France, ca.
1050). The "hurdy-gurdy" also dates from this period. This is a
stringed instrument, much like a modern violin but with a winding handle at the
blunt end. This crank drives an internal disc, which "bows" the
strings continuously from below rather than intermittently from above,
thus producing a continuous "drone" to accompany a main melody fingered
from above. The first organ keyboard appeared at Magdeburg Cathedral towards
the end of the 11th century.
Twelfth
Century: The magnetic compass (1182;
earlier in the Far East).
Thirteenth
Century: 1253
- the decimal system; 1260 - Strasbourg
cathedral organ [complete "with automations" (source)];
1280 the spinning wheel.
Fourteenth
Century: 1310 - European
weight-and-escapement clocks; 1340 - the blast furnace; 1347 - the cannon
(earlier in the Far East); 1391 - the astrolabe.
Nor had Hildebrand been the first
alchemist-pope. One Gerbert
d'Aurillac, later to become Pope Sylvester II (pontiff 999-1003), is known to
have travelled widely in his early ecclesiastical career, and is rumoured to
have acquired various hermetic secrets and skills, which he used to win friends
and see off rivals. One of these devices was a so-called "oracular
bust", a head-and-shoulders automaton, something between an innocent
amusement and a clockwork Delphic oracle. However, there are few hard facts to
go on, so we can only presume (if the thing existed at all) (a) that it was no
more complex than the modern penny arcade attraction [image], and (b) that
it derived its impact thanks to the showmanship of the magus in question.
ASIDE:
The
Internet is awash with reminders that the alchemists actually had two uses for their famed
"philosopher's stone", not just the "transmutation" of base
metals into gold. The second, and often overlooked, search was for the secret
of immortality [check it
out], and the interest in automata may well derive from this.
Gerbert's "talking head" experiment was
replicated, albeit to less spectacularly successful effect, by the English
theologian-scholar Robert Grosseteste some time in the early-to-mid 1200s, and
then again a generation later by one of Grosseteste's students, the monk-alchemist
Roger Bacon (he who had brought the
latest in battlefield alchemy - gunpowder - to Europe from the East). The story
runs that he had somehow come by an ancient Arabic manuscript which contained
the secret whereby "dead metal" could be given "tongue". He
translated this manuscript as best he could, and, together with a colleague
named Bungay, set about making a talking brass head. To cut a long story short,
the two men succeeded, but - through sheer exhaustion - were out of the room
when the thing finally spoke!
ASIDE: The legend of Bacon's brass head entered popular
history thanks to Robert Greene's play "Friar Bacon and Friar Bungay"
(1589). Baldwin's (1905) embellished re-telling of the tale is online [take
me there]. 21st century talking heads look like this:
they, too, mostly tell us what we want to hear.
But we have saved the best story for last, for nowhere
is the mediaeval ambivalence on the science-sorcery issue better seen than in
the case of the Dominican Friar Albertus
Magnus, world authority in his time on such sciences as physics, astronomy,
and biology. Tutor of the young Thomas Aquinas
in 1243, Albertus became Regent of Studies of the Dominican Order in Cologne in
1248, and during the next 30 years wrote books on just about every subject
under the sun, including a 1250 treatise entitled "On Animals", in
which he presented the results of a series of practical dissection studies. He
also (so the stories go) spent his spare time building a speaking automaton.
Unfortunately, there are light and dark reports of everything Albertus did, and
not least of the story of his automaton. On the one hand, we have the orthodox Catholic
Encyclopaedia version of the tale, which tells how Albertus built only a
relatively innocent animated doll, capable of artificial phonation. On the
other hand, there is a darker version of the story, in which he communed with
"angels from the underworld" and used "materials unknown to this
world" to build a speaking, thinking, android, complete with a soul. Even
the name of the mysterious automaton changes from account to account, being Barbiton
in some and Android in others. However, both versions of the story more
or less agree that Aquinas entered Albertus's workshop one day on an
unannounced visit, and was so surprised at being spoken to by a doll that he
decided it must be Satanic, and smashed it to pieces.
ASIDE: No doubt this is a heavily dramatised and much
exaggerated tale of a small-scale (but deadly serious) techno-philosophical
endeavour. Albertus was an expert in the cognitive science of his day, and
would have known as much about speech synthesis, mediaeval style, as Gerbert
had done, and considerably more about how to pre-program and mechanise its
delivery. Our own guess is that he would have combined the established
Alexandrian art of mechanical pre-programming with the newer hurdy-gurdy and/or
vox humana organ-pipe technology [for a quick introduction to the
science of organ stops, click
here]. And he would have had his own textbook of dissections to fall back
on whenever the search for the secrets of artificial life needed inspiration
from the real thing.
Now lest we be accused of wandering seriously
off-topic, the history of the talking head is now the official prehistory of
artificial intelligence. For example Owen Holland, of the University of Essex,
gave a paper at the April 2000 Tucson consciousness conference entitled
"Engineering Artificial Consciousness: You Will Be There When The Brass
Head Speaks", in which he reminded us of Warren McCulloch's ten
commandments of artificial intelligence, the tenth of which was not to let
your attention wander [check
them out]!
3. Late
Renaissance and Enlightenment Materialism: The beginning of the Renaissance proper has been dated with perhaps a
touch too much precision to 29th May 1453. Here is the argument
.....
"One way to date the beginning of the Renaissance
is from May 29, 1453, the day the Turks captured the city of Constantinople and
many Greek-speaking scholars escaped to the West. The scholars brought with
them classical manuscripts in Greek along with the ability to translate the
ancient writings into Latin, the common language of learning in Europe at the
time" (Hellemans and Bunch, 1988, p90).
The upshot was that the availability of knowledge
across Europe started to improve, and as it became more available it became
more reliable into the bargain, as many established disagreements were resolved
by direct empirical investigation. In 1473, for example, Avicenna's Canon of
Medicine was published in Milan, in 1512 Hieronymus of Brunswik published a
textbook treatise on chemical distillation and its uses, in 1543 Vesalius gave
scholars a reliable neuroanatomy to work with, in 1581 Galileo began a
six-decade adventure in practical experimentation, and in 1590 John Napier
started work on his system of logarithms. And, as an inspiration to them all,
there were Leonardo da Vinci's visions of a future based on technology. Da
Vinci's sketches - designs for helicopters, submarines, etc. - are well known,
and include, from around 1495, a sketch for a humanoid robot
.....
ASIDE: Da Vinci's 1495 design was partly constructed in 2002
by the roboticist Mark Rosheim, and Rosheim (2006) [buy
this book] contains pictures and details of the cam-and-follower
escapements by which the actions of the android can be pre-programmed (a technique
which did for analog control what the Bouchon-Falcon-Jacquard system would do
for digital control three centuries later - see below). The biomedical
engineers at the University of Connecticut are also on the case [tell me about this].
In
fact, Da Vinci has two claims to a place on the timeline leading to modern
cognitive science. Some time around 1500, he also sketched a design for an
adding machine built of interlinked, rotating, digit-wheels [image]. It is not known whether he
actually built a machine to go with this design, but Guatelli's (1968)
facsimile has since confirmed its practicability [tell me this story].
Similarly, in 1623 one Wilhelm Schickard is reported to have built a
"calculating clock" capable of adding and subtracting six-digit
numbers, but again no specimen of the machine exists, and again there has been a
20th century facsimile [image]. More
complete details have survived from 1642, when the 19-year French mathematician
Blaise Pascal developed the Pascaline .....
ASIDE:
In modern techno-parlance, the Pascaline has to be classed as a "da
Vinci clone". It consisted of a set of geared counter wheels with a
"tens carry" system, and could record an eight-digit running total. A
number was inserted by rotating the appropriate "column" wheel
(units, tens, hundreds, etc.) with a stylus, and then added to by onward
rotation by cognate column from right to left. The carry system would take care
of turning as many as necessary of the dials to the left of the one being moved
manually [for pictures and a more detailed description, click here].
So by the mid-17th century, the time was ripe for
someone to bring together the Gerbert-Grossteste-Albertus tradition of the
talking android and the da Vinci-Schickard-Pascal tradition of calculating
clockwork, because what you would get if you could do this would be both a
rudimentary science of robotics and some priceless new insights on the
ultimate nature of the biological mind. Specifically, you would have provided
the materialistically minded thinkers of that age with arguably their greatest
ever inspiration, for if fabricated automata were so clever then perhaps we
were all fabrications - fabrications of nature.
And so automata suddenly became the quintessential
test case in the Materialism debate.
ASIDE: Readers unfamiliar with Descartes' writings should
have a quick look at the entry for consciousness,
Descartes' theory of before proceeding.
It was Descartes,
the class-defining dualist, who fired the opening shots in the
"human automaton" debate by identifying the "pores" [=
synapses], "tubules", and "spirits" [= neurotransmitters]
of the brain (Descartes, 1637, 1647). Unfortunately, delays in
publication forced upon him by his church meant that Descartes was unable to
take part personally in the ensuing debate, and Hobbes was therefore
able to put the monist case first .....
MATERIALIST
THEORY #2: Hobbes
opened his "Leviathan" (Hobbes, 1651/1914) with the assertion that
life was "but a motion of limbs", that the heart was "but a
spring", that the nerves were "but so many strings", and that
the joints were "but so many wheels" (Leviathan, p1). He then reviewed the main mental systems - the
senses, imagination, thought, the "passions", etc., etc. - seeking
out the material basis of each. In the event, however, he offered little
specific description of the mechanisms responsible, giving us merely a
Materialism born of vague presumption. The attention to detail in Descartes' Treatise
therefore puts Hobbes to shame in this respect.
There followed a century-long "academic bare
knuckles" debate in which the Cartesians slugged it out with the
Hobbesians. In Britain, this debate was led by Hobbes personally, until his
death in 1679, and was then taken up by the founding fathers of the Royal
Society - the likes of Boyle, Hooke, Wren, Willis. On the Continent, it was led
by the Rationalists Spinoza and Leibniz. For indicative
arguments, see the Leibniz-Bayle and
Leibniz-Boyle debates.
ASIDE:
Readers who have not already come across the Leibniz Mill thought experiment should visit that entry as well,
while the Leibniz moment is upon them. Note that Leibniz actually knew more about mechanism (and therefore its
limitations) than most philosophers, having developed a crank-driven
"stepped drum" of Pascal's calculating machine in 1674. This was
capable of multiplication by repeated addition, went under the name machina
arithmetica, and the experience of turning a pile of cogwheels into a
higher-order but still unthinking
entity must certainly have inspired the mill metaphor.
Then came a rather damning
critique of Materialism by Bishop George Berkeley,
one of the three "great men" of British
Empiricism. Berkeley was responsible in 1710 for resurrecting the classical
challenge about what was matter anyway. He pointed out that what we experienced
as matter bore little resemblance to the real thing (whatever that was) [for
more on this issue, see the entry for reality].
4. Early
Industrial Materialism: Leibniz died
in 1716, two years after his "mill" had reduced a lifetime of
philosophising to a straight-to-the-point five-minute thought experiment. His death was followed in short order by two
particularly noteworthy inventions, both now centrally relevant to cognitive
science. The first of these was the idea of the punched card program. This
clever piece of technology seems to have come more or less simultaneously from
Basile Bouchon in 1725 (using
continuous punched paper) and Jean Philippe Falcon in 1728 (using punched slats), the prepunching serving to
codify the pattern of the weave in advance [see images of both systems]. The
mass production of any repeating woven pattern thus became simple once the
appropriate slats had been produced.
ASIDE: Bouchon was the son of an organ maker, and may well have inherited some
of the old Greek automatic control skills from his father's workshop. Falcon's
machine is on display in the Museum of Arts and Crafts in Paris. In 1805,
another French weaver - Joseph Jacquard
- improved Falcon's system [for technical details, see Section 3 of our e-paper
on "Short-Term
Memory Subtypes in Computing and Artificial Intelligence (Part 1)"],
enabling continuous loops of up to 24,000 instruction cards to be put together.
The Falcon-Jacquard system is cited as standard in histories of computing,
because it reduced a repetitive human craft to an essentially numerical
process, it brought numerical control to a manufacturing industry, and
it involved programming as we nowadays understand it.
The
second important invention was a labour-saving device from the wind-milling industry.
It was the brainchild of one Edward Lee in 1745, and it made it possible to
re-align mills automatically as the direction of the wind veered from moment to
moment. The mechanism consisted of a small "fan-tail" rotor mounted
at the rear of the mill cap, set at a horizontal right angle to the main sails
[image]. As
long as the wind struck the main sails directly, the fan-tail stood idle. When
the wind veered to one side or the other, however, the fan-tail started to
rotate one way or the other, and drove gears which cranked the mill cap back
into the wind again, whereupon the fan-tail fell idle again, of course.
When the wind came from the right, the mill turned to the right - of its own accord - and when the wind
came from the left, the mill turned to the left - of its own accord. The fan-tail was thus an instantiation of what
we know today as a "negative feedback control loop", the principle it
followed was that now known as "homeostasis",
and the science it inspired was that eventually named "la cybernétique".
Coincidentally, even as the millers were sitting back to enjoy their new-found
leisure-time, across the Channel in France the ink was still drying on the
early chapters of the third of our Materialist theories .....
MATERIALIST THEORY #3: History now recognises La Mettrie's (1747/1750) L'Homme Machine
("Man the Machine") as continuing in the Hobbesian tradition. Here,
in his own words, is the essence of La Mettrie's scheme .....
"But
since all the faculties of the soul depend to such a degree on the proper
organization of the brain and of the whole body, that apparently they are but
this organization itself, the soul is clearly an enlightened machine. For finally, even if man alone had received a share of natural law,
would he be any less a machine for that? A few more wheels, a few more
springs than in the most perfect animals, the brain proportionally nearer the
heart and for this very reason receiving more blood - any one of a number of
unknown causes might always produce this delicate conscience so easily wounded,
this remorse which is no more foreign to matter than to thought, and in a word
all the differences that are supposed to exist here. Could the organism then
suffice for everything? Once more, yes; since thought visibly develops with our
organs, why should not the matter of which they are composed be susceptible
of remorse also, when once it has acquired, with time, the faculty of
feeling? The soul is therefore but an empty word, of which no one has any idea,
and which an enlightened man should only use to signify the part in us that
thinks" (bold highlighting added).
Not surprisingly, La Mettrie's work simply
re-polarised the dualist-monist debate, to the extent that there was no longer
any debate - you either believed that humans were mechanisms or you did not.
Like left versus right in politics, you voted with your viscera, not with your
head. Nor were there even any reliable data for the genuinely undecided to fall
back on, because when you operationalised or simulated thought it ceased to be
thought [Leibniz's mill again]. Automata, for example, were still manifestly
just expensive puppets, and there was no decisive test case to swing doubters
one way or the other; the "pilot of
the soul" remained as elusive as it had been two thousand years
beforehand. Immaterialists of all persuasion simply rubbed their hands with
glee and smiled their I-told-you-sos.
And then came Kant,
with an entire - and still unresolved - dimension to the problem of mind, and a
British amateur engineer named Charles Babbage,
with an entire - and still evolving - dimension to the problem of brain.
5. Modern
Materialism:
Two more or less simultaneous publications, one at cognitive science's philosophical
brow and the other at its physiological heart, set off the close of the 18th
century as being qualitatively different to the close of the 17th. The first of
these publications was a microscopic analysis of the mind presented by the
philosopher Immanuel Kant in his Critique
of Pure Reason (Kant, 1781/1787), and its importance stems from its
emphasis on the complexities of phenomenology [for more on which, see the
entry for consciousness, Kant's theory of]. The second epoch-defining
publication was Galvani's (1791) "De
Viribus Electricitatis", a report into the fundamentally electrical
nature of nervous transmission. This ground-breaking research demonstrated in essence that the muscle tissue of a
"dead" animal could be caused to twitch by the application of an
electric current. Taken together, Kant's Critique
and Galvani's readily replicable laboratory demonstration threw a whole new
light on the central problem of mental
philosophy. Henceforward, anyone wanting to be a successful Materialist would have
to become not just a successful phenomenologist [no mean feat], but a skilled
physiologist into the bargain. Indeed, Kant's phenomenology and Galvani's
"animal electricity" stand as the first two of four 19th century
sciences which have now been taken under the cognitive science umbrella. The
third of these new sciences was neuropsychology .....
ASIDE: Neurology is what physicians are
doing every time they use the routine neurological examination to assess
the extent of the injuries to a patient's nervous system. As such, it is an
application area which goes back to Hippocrates and beyond. If you specialise
in neurology, going out of your way to acquire the very latest in assessments
and treatments, then you become a neurologist.
Neuropsychology, by contrast, is barely medicine at all, in the accepted sense
of the word. Where neurology is medicine of the brain, neuropsychology sets out
to assess and repair the mind, and since
nobody has yet decided how the mind works neuropsychologists have to do nine parts
mental philosophy for every one part hard neuroscience. Neuropsychology is
what neurologists used to do as an adjunct to the neurology, but now leave to
allied professionals. Freud, for example, managed to be a neurologist, a
neuropsychologist, and a psychiatrist,
but the sheer volume of modern knowledge would have forced him to specialise.
It is also necessary nowadays to distinguish between clinical and theoretical
neuropsychology. Clinical
neuropsychology is the use in psychiatry, criminology, speech and
language therapy, etc., of neuropsychologically inspired psychometric
assessments and the construction of theoretically grounded remediation
techniques and approaches, whilst cognitive
neuropsychology attempts to provide those bodies of clinicians and
practitioners with the necessary theoretical underpinning, not least on the mind-brain
debate and the localisation of function debate.
Among the leading neurologists of the early 19th
century, we have Sir Charles Bell in Britain and Francois Magendie in France.
Bell published "New Anatomy of the Brain" in
1811. In it he analysed the organisation of the spinal cord and proposed a
fundamental distinction between sensory and motor functions. The motor tracts,
he claimed, ran ventrally within the cord. Magendie confirmed Bell's analysis
in 1822, and demonstrated also that the sensory tracts ran dorsally. This
combination of principles has since become known as the "Bell-Magendie Law".
ASIDE:
To see a simple schematic diagram of the dorsal ascending and ventral
descending pathways, click
here. To see a more detailed cross-section through the
spinal cord, showing the component tracts, click here.
The
most important early physician-neuropsychologists was
Marie-Jean-Pierre Flourens. Flourens had been following the early
localisation of function debate, and came to the opinion that it would never be
possible to localise brain function precisely. In his view, many of its
functions were far too complex and all-embracing to pin down in this way.
Flourens' position comes out well in the following quotation
.....
"Each
part of the nervous system [] has a proper function; and that is what makes it
a distinct part: but the activity of each of these parts affects the activities
of all the others; and that is what makes them parts of a particular system.
[What matters] is the way each distinct part of this system contributes to the
common activity" (Flourens, 1824; modern neuropsychology is still
vigorously debating this very issue, which remains to be resolved).
The fourth major area - as if the first three were
not genius enough - was the birth of computing.
ASIDE: We have covered the history
of computing in considerable detail elsewhere, so to avoid pointless
duplication, we refer readers to Sections 3 and 6 of our e-resource "Short-Term Memory
Subtypes in Computing and Artificial Intelligence (Part 1)". Suffice
it here to note that working mechanical computers date from the mid-19th
century and the data processing industry from the 1890s.
Given the accelerating pace
of discovery, it is not surprising that the 19th century brought a succession
of fresh opinions on the Mind-Brain debate, and the first definitive history of
Materialism (Lange,
1866). One of the fresh minds was Büchner (1879), who likened the momentary
direction of the mind to the geometric resultant of a number of force vectors
in mechanics. Sadly, his explanation of the "particular go" of the
resulting system remained as vague an appeal to consensus as ever, thus .....
"A spirit without body is as unimaginable as
electricity or magnetism without metallic or other substances on which these
forces act. The animal soul is a product of external influences, without which
it would never have been called into existence [..... and w]ith
the decay and dissolution of its material dissolution of its material
substratum, through which alone it has acquired a conscious existence and
become a person [.....] the spirit must cease to exist" (Büchner, 1879, Force
and Matter, p196; quoted in Hamilton, p276; our emphasis).
The second half of the 19th century also saw the
Golden Age of neuropsychology, with contributions from Broca, Wernicke, Hughlings Jackson, Meinert, Kussmaul, and Freud.
But then, in 1896, the goalposts moved
again! This time the key development happened in a small laboratory at the
Paris Natural History Museum, where one Antoine Becquerel was checking through
the museum's stock of mineral samples to see if he could find any which
naturally emitted the then-recently-reported x-rays. He found no x-rays, but
chanced instead upon the fact that compounds of uranium were capable of
exposing photographic plates despite their protective wrapping. It took
only weeks of follow-up experimentation to demonstrate that this particular
type of matter was giving off some form of penetrating "radiation",
and in less than a decade it had become apparent that some atoms were not
a-tomic [i.e. indivisible] at all: already provisionally named
"radio-active" by the Curies, they were disintegrating before your
eyes! Max Planck had even named the unit of this decay, choosing the term
"quantum" to express its step-wise regularity (Planck, 1900). So here
again we had our confidence in the fundamental reliability of matter shaken.
Not only could it never be directly seen, but it was in any event little more
than a nuclear soup in a state of constant flux, even to the extent that Popper
(1977) was able to suggest abandoning "the
idea of a substance or essence" (p7) altogether. Then in the 1970s it
occurred to consciousness theorists that perhaps they should seek the
"particular go" of the mind could be found by taking the reductionist
approach down to sub-atomic levels .....
MATERIALIST
THEORY #4: Just as the atomistic theory of the mind came along just after the
atomistic theory of physics [See Theory #1 above], so too with the sub-atomic
theory of the mind and the sub-atomic theory of physics. Scaruffi (2006 online) credits the
original notion to the biologist Alfred Lotka as early as 1924. Lotka, he
explains, saw control of otherwise random quantal release as the essence of an
information processing system. Writing at the height of the Behaviourist era,
however, few psychologists paid much attention to Lotka's speculation, and as
the role of ion transport systems in neurotransmission emerged over the ensuing
half century, quantum physics was overshadowed in favour of the more
conventional electrochemistry. The next step in Scaruffi's telling of the story
was the physicist Evan Walker's "synaptic tunnelling" model (Walker,
1977, 2000), which posits an as-yet-undemonstrated role for quantum physics in
determining when a given synapse is ready to transmit. Similar proposals were
made in the 1980s by Frölich (e.g., 1986) and Marshall (1989), this time relying
on a quantum effect known as "Bose-Einstein condensation". The
potential value of all these proposed mechanisms is that they address the brain
at the level of the individual "flip-flop",
however, since this is the sort of extreme reductionist approach which created
the explanatory gap in the first place, we doubt it is very like to
close it. In other words, while quantum physics may eventually allow one to
state the "particular go" of the brain,
it will not, we suspect, add much to our understanding of the mind. Nevertheless, the notion is still
being heavily promoted - click here to see
a brief review of the competing proposals.
The 1980s also saw a
proliferation of "-isms" in the mind-brain debate, as cognitive
scientists tried to decide where they really did stand on the issue. Not
content with a simple choice between Materialism and Immaterialism, they added
"Emergentism", "Emergent Dualism", "Psychophysical
Parallelism", "Epiphenomenalism", and others too numerous to
mention.
ASIDE: As an impressionable
non-philosopher, we remember being quite taken by Central State Materialism when we first read about
it, and have given details of this in a separate entry, q.v.
We close with one final look at automata, because
they, too, have come a long way. Check
out this image, for example. That was Johnny Five, from the 1986 movie "Short Circuit". He
looks bright enough, sure, but - like Gerbert's talking head [above] - he was
worked almost entirely by remote control! He was literally too good to be true.
Now
take a look at Kismet, one of a range of state-of-the-art research
projects being carried out at MIT. Kismet
and Johnny Five look like cousins,
but Kismet is for real - it has much
more going on inside. It can, for example, mimic a number of human emotional
expressions (especially
those involving eyebrows). Then there is the Honda-Kawasaki ASIMO [image]. It can walk, has colour
vision, face recognition, gesture recognition, and speech, and can even obey
simple commands, but it has little intelligence, and no volition [= free
will] at all! QRIO [image] is
Sony's answer to ASIMO. It can do most things ASIMO can do, but has better hand
and finger control. There is even a famous publicity image of four identical
QRIOs playing Ave Maria on hand-bells, as a party-piece [show me]!
Nowadays we even have robots made only out of spots of light on a display
screen. Here's
just such a "software agent" - a virtual android with lots of
intelligence and no complicated mechanical bits at all, just a lot of
pre-formed binary; not unlike one of Bouchon's weaving patterns, in fact, save
that the method of delivery of the final image involves less wool! She's an
"avatar", the BBC's Ananova, virtual newsreader and
prototype "cyberbabe".
ASIDE: Avatars are already at work
in the service of humankind. For their clinical use in the treatment of autistic
spectrum disorders, see the entry for the AS Interactive project.
And what
of the future? Well eventually the brass head will speak, do not doubt it, and when it
does there will be no danger of it going unnoticed [it may well be kept under
the cloak of military secrecy, but that is a different issue]. What we shall
not know, however, is what to do with it when it does speak. What, in other
words, will it be? A servant? A God?
An idol? A weapon of mass
destruction? That, perhaps, is when the real philosophy is going to be
needed, so we had better give the very last word to the immaterialist, Theodore
Christlieb (Modern Doubt, 1874, p156) .....
"In good sooth, the
materialists are the most dangerous enemies of progress the world has ever
seen"
MATS: See Mehrabian Achieving Tendency Scale.
Mature Defenses: See defense mechanisms.
May,
Rollo:
[American existentialist psychologist (1909-1994).] [Click for external biography]
We touch briefly upon May's work in the entries for aggression, humanistic
theory and and aggression, psychodynamic theory and.
Maze Following
(Visual): [See firstly executive function and dysexecutive syndrome.]
ENTRY TO FOLLOW
MBCT: See mindfulness-based cognitive therapy.
MBSR: See mindfulness-based stress reduction.
MBTI: See Myers-Briggs Type Indicator.
McCullough's Ten Commandments: See materialism
and underlying mechanism (2) and the onward link.
McDougall, William: [British (later American) psychologist
(1871-1938).] [Click for
external biography] McDougall is noteworthy in the context of the present
glossary for his work on aggression, institutionalisation of.
MCST: See Wisconsin
Card Sorting Test.
Mead, George Herbert: [American social psychologist (1863-1931).] [Click for external
biography] Mead is noteworthy in
the context of the present glossary for his work on self.
Meadow, Sir Samuel Roy: [British paediatrician (1933-).]
[Click for external biography]
Meadow is noteworthy in the context of
the present glossary for his work on Munchausen syndrome by proxy
and sudden infant death syndrome.
Meadow's Syndrome: See Munchausen syndrome by proxy.
Meaning:
Meaning is "that which is intended to be or actually is expressed or
indicated [.....] Of language, a sentence, word, etc.: the signification, sense,
import [.....] The intended sense of (a person's) words" (O.E.D.). More
analytically, it is that which a symbol signifies,
or a proposition predicates. When
that meaning can be expressed verbally, it will present as a number of related
propositions, combining to produce upon demand a dictionary definition of a
target word. It is thus what the Greek philosophers termed logos, and needs to be rendered as "account of" or
"formula for" (Lawson-Tancred, 1986, p117). A serious philosophical
problem then arises, namely that the full significance of a concept is
coloured by a potentially limitless number of onward associations, thanks to
the network nature of our semantic memories. For example, the nub of the
dictionary definition of "pen" is that it is "a writing
tool" (O.E.D.), although what this definition does not include (and never
could cover, because it would need to be tailored personally to each individual
reader's specific past history) are the associations which "pen"
might bring to mind. This is what Titchener (1910) had in mind when he wrote:
"One mental process is the meaning of another mental process if it is that
other's context" (p367) [it is also worth noting en passant that the essential individuality of meaning is the
central tenet of Personal Construct
Theory]. William James drew attention to the problem that the meaning of
any thought was always going to be "one of those evanescent and
'transitive' facts of mind which introspection
cannot [reach]" (James, 1890, pI.472).
Mehrabian, Albert: [American psychologist.] [Homepage]
Mehrabian is noteworthy in the context of the present glossary for his work on body language and the Mehrabian Achieving Tendency Scale.
Meinong, Alexius: [Austrian philosopher-psychologist (1853-1920).] [Click for external
biography] Meinong studied under Brentano
at Vienna, before going on to establish the Graz Psychological Institute in
1894. His emphasis on the need for empirical support during
psychological theorizing helped psychology consolidate its
then-recently-acquired status as a science. His most influential early works
were "On Assumptions" (Meinong, 1902, 1910/1983) and "On
Gegenstandstheory" (Meinong, 1904). [See now consciousness, Meinong's theory of.]
Memory for Gist: [See firstly gist
and Bartlett (1932).] Understanding a complex narrative or a
technical argument requires what the man in the street would call
"grasping" or "getting the gist" of a very deep message;
what Bartlett (1932) called the "bare outline" (p75) or "the
general form, or scheme, or plan" (p83) behind the words. [Compare story
memory and Thorndike
(1977).]
Memory Impairment: Memory dysfunction is a major element in differential diagnosis under
DSM-IV, and - to be judged
pathological - must be "sufficiently severe so as to be clinically
significant" (First, Frances, and Pincus, 1995, p83).
Memory Span: A memory test in
which subjects are presented with strings of test items for short term rehearsal.
Performance levels off in normals as soon as the string exceeds about seven
items in length, and is one of the first abilities to fail following
neurological trauma.
Memory,
Physiological versus Functional Types: Just as there are many types
of building but only a few types of brick, cognitive science can identify many functional types of knowledge but only
three underlying physical memory types,
that is to say, memory types which can be pinned down to concrete anatomical or
physiological structures and/or processes. The three recognised physical memory
types are as follows .....
Structural - Long-Term Memory (LTM): This type of
memory derives ultimately from networks of neurons wired together by physical
neural fibres and organised into "processing modules". It supports a
large number of conditioning and knowledge types, and, although it takes some
time to establish itself, is then relatively durable. The adjective
"long" indicates a lifespan between an hour
or two and several decades.
Electrical - Short-Term Memory (STM): This type of
memory contains transient knowledge, that is to say, information on its way
into, or out of, LTM. Physiologically it derives from momentary fluctuations in
ionic electrical potential - both spiked and graded - within neurons, whilst
psychologically it accounts for the momentary contents of the cognitive system,
and, presumably, of the small fraction thereof which is our consciousness. The
adjective "short" indicates a lifespan between say a few milliseconds
and, say, two or three seconds, although "reverberatory" feedback
within or between modules might, on occasion, artificially extend this.
Electrochemical - Medium-Term Memory (not
usually abbreviated): This type of memory does not contain any knowledge at
all, but rather maintains pointers (sometimes called "tags") to
recently activated points within LTM. Biologically this
"touch-and-glow" ability derives from synaptic sensitisation
processes such as "calcium switching" and "second
messenger" neurotransmission, and psychologically it is the key to
interfacing the electrical and the structural aspects of memory, and thus
maintaining the continuity and coherence of thought. The adjective
"medium" indicates a period between, say, two or three seconds and
one or two hours. [See under protein kinase studies in the body of this
glossary.]
As for the functional memory types which the
physical systems combine to provide our minds with, non-psychologists may find
it useful to begin by looking up perceptual memory, episodic memory,
and semantic memory, and newcomers to neuroscience should familiarise
themselves firstly with neuroanatomy, and then move on to neurotransmission
and synapse.
Memory Trace: Same as engram
(which use).
Mental Capacity Act, 2005: This Act states that every
adult has the right to make his or her own decisions and must be assumed to
have capacity to do so unless it is proved otherwise. They also have the right
to be supported in enforcing that decision, even
if the outcome seems unwise.
Mental Model: This is the received modern term for the
accumulation of long-term memory structures, most probably of all possible
memory types, which documents the layout of the external world. The concept has been very heavily influenced by the
work of Philip Johnson-Laird, Stuart Professor of Psychology at Princeton
University. Johnson-Laird wrote his first major papers on the subject in the
early 1980s (Johnson-Laird, 1981; 1983), however the term goes back at least to
the 1940s, thus .....
"[While] as a rule mere objects evoke, in
themselves, little response, anything which in the light of our previous
knowledge puzzles us or defeats our insight or suggests new possibilities may
evoke a very definite response. We want then to find some scheme in which our
various experiences combine to produce patterns in us [..... which .....] can
become developed to the point where their relevance to one another becomes
functional; in consciousness this is indicated by ideas 'striking' us []. We
then have a mental model of a possible event in the external world
....." (Craik, undated pre-1945, in Sherwood, 1966,
p72.)
Mental
Philosophy: See philosophy, mental.
Mental
Verbs: A relatively small class of verbs describing the basic metacognitive states and operations of
the mind, whose study is central both to modern cognitive philosophy and many branches
of paediatric and adult clinical psychology. Specifically, "we may call
those verbs mental that express propositional attitudes like believing,
intending, desiring, hoping, knowing, perceiving, noticing, remembering, and so
on" (Davidson, 1970, p83). [For examples, see the separate entries for mental verbs (factive) and mental verbs (non-factive).]
Mental Verbs
(Factive): [See firstly mental verbs.] "A term used in the
classification of verbs, referring to a verb which takes a complement clause,
and where the speaker presupposes the truth of the proposition expressed in
that clause. For example, know, agree,
realise, etc. are 'factive verbs' (or 'factives'): in She knows that the cat is in the garden, the speaker presupposes
that the cat is in the garden" (Crystal, 2003, p175). Such verbs appear in
normal development from around two years of age, beginning with "to
know" and "to think". As classified by Kiparsky and Kiparsky
(1970), the factives are one of the two main types of mental verbs (the other
being mental verbs (non-factive)).
Mental Verbs
(Non-Factive): [Sometimes
"contrafactive".] [See firstly mental
verbs (factive).] As classified by Kiparsky and Kiparsky (1970), the
non-factives are one of the two main types of mental verbs (the other being mental verbs (factive)). They are
mental verbs describing indefinite states of mind such as "to
suspect", "to doubt", "to wish", "to
pretend", and "to imagine".
Mentalese:
See language of thought.
Mereological
Supervenience: [See firstly supervenience.] Mereological
supervenience is "the doctrine that the character of a whole is
supervenient upon the properties and relationships holding for its parts"
(Kim, 1993, p113). Kim goes on to point out (a) that this sort of supervenience
will always have to cross two domains by definition, "one domain
consisting of wholes, and another consisting of their parts" (Ibid.), and (b) that we still have a lot
of work to do in deciphering how this sort of supervenience works in practice
[although the possibility of biological semaphores
and busy pins offers some grounds for early optimism here.]
Mesmer,
Franz: [Austrian physician
(1734-1815).] [Click for
external biography] See Mesmerism.
Mesmerism: This is the at-the-time-popular name for the system
of hypnosis devised as a experimental medical
treatment by Mesmer in the 1770s.
The system involved attaching magnets to patients and then having them swallow
preparations containing iron. Mesmer claimed improvements for a number of
ailments, and attributed these to a mysterious property which he named
"animal magnetism". He published his technique in "Mémoire sur la Découverte du
Magnétisme Animal" (Mesmer, 1779), but a commission of investigation
set up by King Louis XVI concluded in 1784 that there was no true physical
influence at work, merely the effects of suggestion.
Metabolic Pumping: [See firstly random
molecular movement.] Our bodies are made up of billions of cells, each one
surrounded by a porous cell membrane. The passing of chemicals across
these membranes due to osmosis is a significant biological problem because if
steps were not taken to prevent it, the cytoplasm within the cell would
either gain fluid from its surroundings (thereby becoming diluted, even to the
point of splitting the cell membrane open), or else lose fluid to its
surroundings (thereby becoming thickened and unable to carry out its normal
metabolic tasks). Now evolution seems to have solved the problem of porous
membranes in a number of ways. For example, one method was to keep the
concentration of the cytoplasm and its surrounding fluids equal. Another was to
use thicker membranes, such as when Schwann cells provide a myelin
sheath to the axons of myelinated neurons. However, the most sophisticated
method of all was to develop pores in the cell wall capable of chemically
forcing the unwanted particles back out again as they invaded (or the wanted
ones back in again as they escaped). This process consumes energy, however, for
which reason it is known as metabolic pumping. A metabolic pump is thus
a device within the cell membrane which picks up particles from one side
of the membrane and actively transports them to the other. Provided it is
pumping in the right direction, it can be used to counteract the effects of
osmosis. It is conventional to specify the particle concerned when the pump is
named. The neuron's sodium pump, for example, pushes
sodium ions outwards so as to counteract the natural inflow due to random
molecular movement. Dean (1941) has been credited with having first
suggested active metabolic pumping of sodium ions in this way.
Metacognition: [Literally, "cognition after or about
cognition".] In its broadest sense, "metacognition" is the act
of turning the focus of one's mental faculties onto those mental faculties
themselves. It is thus "thinking about thinking", or "knowing
about knowing", or "making judgments about judgments", as when
we say "I am certain of my facts", or "It's taking me longer to
remember things nowadays". The term started to become popular in the late
1970s, following its introduction by Flavell (1976). The underlying construct,
however, is far older, being seen in many (probably all) of the early theories
of consciousness and self. Here are a few examples from elsewhere in this glossary .....
consciousness, Aristotle's theory of - see the notion of aesthesis koine and
the problem of infinite regress.
consciousness, Brentano's theory of - see the notions of Wahrnehmung and Beobachtung.
consciousness, Hegel's theory of - see Hegel's point about the mind possessing an individuality which
knows its own individuality.
consciousness, Kant's theory of - see Kant's point about the Ich Denke.
Flavell (1979) defines metacognitive knowledge as
"that segment of your (a child's, an adult's) stored world knowledge that
has to do with people as cognitive creatures" (p906), and he sees
successful cognitive monitoring as requiring the interaction of such knowledge
with a succession of appropriate experiences. The notion of metacognition as a
sort of mental quality controller -
that there was a discrete skill in a mind watching itself at work - was then
turned into a formal theory of clinical practice in the work of Mary Main (Main
and Goldwyn, 1984, et seq.) [for more on which see the separate entry for metacognitive monitoring]. Coming right
up to date, metacognition remains one of the hot topics of modern cognitive
science, not least because it is one of the principal functional areas for those
developing the next generation of artificial minds. WHERE TO NEXT:
For more on the classical problems of explaining cognition EITHER continue with
the Kant link above OR address many of the same problems in consciousness,
Heidegger's theory of, OR come right up-to-date with consciousness,
Dretske's theory of. For more on the underlying mechanisms, see meta-representation.
For more on the clinical relevance of (defects in) metacognition, see metacognitive monitoring. For more on artificial mind, see false belief test, artificial intelligence and.
Metacognitive Monitoring: [See firstly metacognition
and attachment, personality
disorders and.] This is the hypothetical higher order control process
behind Main and Goldwyn's (1984) notion that "the quality of the
infant's attachment to the parent" appears to be significantly related (a)
to "the adult's reconstruction of his or her attachment history", and
(b) to "the child's later representation of self and others" (Main,
1991, p127). Main and Goldwyn (1984) had been studying the
"intergenerational effect" in child abuse [for more on which, see toxic parenting and cognitive deficit]
and had noted that there was still "much to learn about the specific
mechanism" (p204) of transmission. Here is a description of the problem
they faced .....
"From the time of its first discovery, the child
abuse syndrome has been associated with a history of the parent's own
experience of abuse in childhood [citations]. An early report described a
pattern of three generations of child-battering in some families studied, and a
pattern of child neglect or child battering crossing at least two generations
in other families [citation]. [.....] Studies of the child-rearing histories of
abusive parents converge, in sum, to reveal 'a consistent pattern of
aggressive, physically punitive, childhood experiences' [citation]" (Main
and Goldwyn, 1984, p204).
Main and Goldwyn therefore turned their research gaze
onto the "behavioural resemblance" between abused children and their
abusing parents, and at whether this indicated causally important differences
between the abusing and the non-abusing sectors of the population at large.
They began by reviewing the "largely discouraging or contradictory"
(p205) literature on the subject, noting as follows .....
"Seemingly, only two conclusions could be drawn.
These were, first, that abusing parents suffer a general difficulty with the
control of aggression, one which extends beyond the episodes of abuse of a
particular child [citations]. Second, abusing parents tend to be both
personally and socially isolated from the rest of the community and from
extended family resources [citations] [, much of it] self-imposed" (Main
and Goldwyn, 1984, p205)
They then found precisely the sort of strong behavioural
resemblances they had set out to find .....
"[We] found several aspects of a mother's failure
to integrate her past experiences significantly related to her infant's
avoidance. If a mother insisted that she was unable to recall her childhood,
her infant was significantly likely to avoid her. If a mother idealised her
rejecting mother, her infant was also likely to avoid her. But if the mother
expressed resentment and anger toward her mother during the interview, and if
she was coherent regarding her own feelings and experiences surrounding
attachment, her infant was unlikely to avoid her. Thus the child's avoidance
of its mother as assessed in infancy bore a systematic relationship to the
mother's efforts to describe her own childhood experiences,
and particularly to apparent distortions in mother's cognitive processes.
These points can be illustrated through an attention to particular cases. One
mother [.....] described her mother as 'a good one' and said they had a fine
relationship. When asked what she had done when upset in childhood, she
answered that she had usually run outside. She also recalled an episode in
which she had broken her hand but had been afraid to tell her mother, for fear
she would be angry. She received a high score for frequency of insisting she
could not remember her childhood, a high score for rejection by her mother, and
a high score for idealisation of her mother. Her infant was extremely avoidant of her" (p214; emphasis added).
Main (1991) explains that the relationship between a
person's behaviour and their attachment history is highly complex, and adapts
Bowlby's (1973) "internal mental model" as describing the accumulated
conceptualisations of the self and the world within which it exists. She then
notes as follows .....
"Pressed to describe and evaluate their
attachment experiences and relations, insecure individuals frequently present a
jumble of contradictory thoughts, feelings, and intentions which can only
loosely be described as a 'model'" (p132).
In order to account for this sort of "incoherence
of ideation regarding attachment" (p132), Bowlby admitted the possibility
of "multiple models", including unconscious ones, even if that meant
taking different interpretations of given aspects of reality. Main offers the
inherently contradictory examples of both fearing and hoping that one's father
might leave home, and both approving and disapproving of the quality of one's
mother's mothering. She then identifies in the debate over childhood
representation the same sort of distinction which Kant had had in mind
when distinguishing the noumenon from the phenomenon. Young
children, she points out routinely fail to distinguish "'reality' (which
can never be directly comprehended)" (p134) from "our limited and
diverse representational grasp of that 'reality'" (ibid.). She then presents her core argument, as follows
.....
"The regulation
of cognition, or metacognitive
monitoring, includes planning activities, monitoring them, and checking
outcomes. It necessarily includes the self-regulation of knowledge which should
occur when the thinker becomes aware of contradictions between presently held
ideas, a state which ideally ought to lead to cognitive reorganisation
[citations]. [.....] In contrast to the regulation of cognition, knowledge about cognition refers to
second-order cognition [rather] than the representation itself. Thus the simple
proposition, 'I am an unworthy person' is not an example of metacognition,
whereas the thought that 'I am a person who thinks that I am an unworthy person
rather frequently' is a second-order representation and an example of
metacognitive knowledge. Metacognitive knowledge is described by Brown et al
[(1983)] as 'relatively stable, statable, often fallible, and late-developing
information that human thinkers have about their own cognitive processes and
those of others'. It is, in fact, only when learners have acquired some
appreciation of the fallible nature of knowledge that they can consider their
own cognitive processes as objects of reflection" (p134).
Main believes that this important ability to
"step back" in order to consider one's own cognitive processes may
appear as young as three years of age, but appears in "most (but not
all)" (p134) by age six years. She also adopts Markman's (1984)
"dual-coding deficit hypothesis". This holds that young children,
working as they do to a simple model of reality, are poorly equipped to fit one
item into two categories (as with the item <man> who is both a <father>
and a <doctor>). Having ensured that these notions are fresh in her
readers' minds, Main then reports her experience with a group of six-year-old
children who had been interviewed regarding their understanding as to the
nature of thought. Main had hypothesised that insecure children would have
difficulty understanding the private nature of thought. She had studied 15
subjects, 9 secure, 3 insecure-avoidant, and 3 insecure-ambivalent, and
reported provisionally as follows .....
"All of the children who were secure or avoidant with
mother gave reasonable answers to questions regarding the nature and privacy of
thought. Most children gave adequate responses to the first question (what is a
thought), and all located thoughts in their brain, mind, or heads. [Asked if]
they had [recurrent thoughts], most children gave cursory answers and said no.
Avoidant children were restricted in their answers and apparently in their
interest, while the secure children were more often thoughtful, fluid, and
engaged. [.....] In keeping with our hypothesis, we found that all three of the
insecure-ambivalent children (and no others) stated that others knew what they
were thinking when they could not see them ('my mom ... she's psychic ... she
knows I'm thinking she wouldn't be so mean'), and that they themselves had the
same powers ('I'm psychic too')" (Main, 1991, pp147-148).
Here are some specimen responses
.....
Insecure-Avoidant: "Do other
people know what you are thinking when they can't see you? [.....] They might,
if they couldn't see me, if I was lost, they might know that I was thinking
that I wanted to go home. Do you know
what other people are thinking when you can't see them? No" (Main,
1991, p149).
Insecure-Ambivalent:
"Do other people know what you are thinking when they can't see you? Mmhm. Yes. They know what I'm thinking. Who? Somebody. I promised not to tell.
[.....] How do they know? Easy. I think of them
and then they think of me. Do you know
what other people are thinking when you can't see them? Yes. Who? I can't tell. Do you know what thoughts look like? Yeah, they're big and
round" (ibid.).
Secure: "What is a
thought? You think like, uh, you think like something's gonna happen and
you don't know. You think but you don't know. Where are thoughts? Thoughts are in your head. [.....] Do other people know what you are thinking
when they can't see you? No
[.....]. Do you know what other
people are thinking when you can't see them? No. Maybe they aren't even thinking. That's a possibility. (Laughs)
That's what I THOUGHT. That they might not be thinking. Do you know what
thoughts look like? I don't know. Like movies? Maybe.
What else do thoughts look like? Like teeny little things (gestures to
show how tiny, closing thumb and forefinger), and there's all these teeny
little things and like those are all the things in the whole wide world. All
those tiny things you can think of" (ibid.).
Main and Hesse (1990) have considered how easy it is
for parents' unresolved traumatic experiences to corrupt their own children's
attachment experiences. They speculated that both frightening and frightened
behaviour on the part of a parent can very quickly have a pathological effect
on the way an infant learns to experience and handle its own emotions, thus
.....
"We suggest that a parent suffering from
unresolved mourning may still be frightened by her loss experiences. As a result, she may display an anxiety that could in turn be
frightening to her infant" (Main and Hesse, 1990, p174).
To help establish how that anxiety might be
communicated, Main and Hesse conducted a further analysis of their data, and
noted the following three behavioural channels, "each of which seems to us
likely to frighten an infant, either by being directly threatening or by indicating
fright on the part of the parent" (p175).
ASIDE: Readers who are unfamiliar with the rich variety of
options available for non-verbal communication should check out Section 3.2 of
the companion resource "Communication
and the Naked Ape" before proceeding. Note especially the use of
non-verbal "back-channels" as mechanisms for delivering the constant feedback
necessary for effective conversation.
Here are Main and Hesse's three pathogenic communicative
behaviours .....
Unusual
Vocal Patterns: The first "side
channel" of anxiety-communication is the human voice, not for the words it
produces, but for the intonation with which it produces them, thus .....
"These include: (1) simultaneous voicing and
de-voicing intonation (especially during greeting [.....]) leading
to an ominous, or 'haunted', tone or effect. Thus the parent may greet the
infant with a simultaneously voiced and de-voiced 'Hi'. This is a breathy,
extended, falling intonation which can be recreated by saying 'Hi' while
pulling in on the diaphragm. (2) Parent's voice has sudden marked drop in
intonation to deep or low pitch. When marked, such changes are startling,
especially when the speaker is a woman whose pitch and intonation suddenly seem
to belong to a male speaker" (Main and Hesse, 1990, p175).
Unusual
Movement Patterns: The second side channel is the movement which accompanies speech, thus .....
"These include: (1) parent
suddenly moves object or own face very close to infant's face ('looming'). (2)
Parent's movements or postures are part of a pursuit sequence. (3) Parent
presents conflicting signals by, for example, calling infant while standing
[in] a threatening posture. (4) Unpredictable invasions of the infant's
personal space, as the parent's hands suddenly sliding from behind or across
the infant's face or throat. (5) Parent's handling [suggests] extreme timidity.
(6) Parent is extremely responsive to any indications of
rejection on the part of the infant" (op. cit., p175).
Unusual
Speech Content: The third pathogenic
communicative behaviour is gross inappropriacy of content, as illustrated on
the following extract .....
"These include: (1) parent implies that infant's
actions could have harmful consequences - (a) 'You'll kill that little
(stuffed) bear if you do that!' (b) 'Uuuohh! (Frightened
intake of breath as infant moves toy car across bare floor.) Gonna have
an accident! Everybody's gonna get killed!' (2) Sudden initiation of games with
a frightening speech content, if accompanied by an unusual, frightening,
pattern of movement and intonation - 'I'm gonna get you!' (3) Direct
indications of fear of the infant, as, for example, backing away from the infant
while directing the infant not to follow in a stammering, apprehensive voice -
'Don't follow, d-don't'" (op. cit., p176).
WHERE TO NEXT: Worryingly, there is no
single body of theory capable of commenting on the above. The pathogenic behaviours
described certainly seem to be "bad habits" rather than deliberate
attempts to frighten or do harm, so the generic treatment would be to try to
develop better social and communication skills on the part of the parent [for
more on which, see the entry for social
skills training]. However, the possibility (indeed probability) remains
that the problem is deeper, even, than that - specifically, with a parental cognitive deficit, perhaps, and/or personality defect. Worse still, it is
not possible to engage theoretically with the interaction of deep (i.e.,
pre-verbal) parental motivation and surface parental speech without getting to
grips with two major topics in linguistic
philosophy, namely pragmatics and speech acts, and
these are both highly abstract and highly technical theoretical areas.
Note also the functions of "mirroring" and "shaping" in
normal early mother-child interaction, and reflect upon the role played by such
simple behaviours in the formation of thought and self.
Metacontrol:
In the context of the lateralisation of function debate, this is Levy and
Trevarthen's (1976) term for the phenomenon of hemispheric dominance [see consciousness, Gazzaniga's theory of],
and implies that one hemisphere is elevated to be "a controller of controllers"
on the grounds that it would be impractical to have two equal "minds"
in one body. More generally, the term can safely be applied to any vertically
related pair of modules in a control
hierarchy.
Metaphysics: [Greek meta = "after/beyond", with phusika = "natural things".] Metaphysics is "that
branch of speculative inquiry which treats of the first principles of things,
including such concepts as being, substance, essence, time, space, cause,
identity, etc.; theoretical philosophy as the ultimate science of Being and
Knowing" (O.E.D.). Alternatively, "metaphysics is concerned with
basic questions about the nature of reality: what caused the universe? what is the nature of space and time? are
all events caused? ....." (Kitcher, 1996, xxvii).
As such, Metaphysics is the title of one of Aristotle's surviving
classics, and the primary source-work for Aristotelian "first
philosophy", being so-called because it is discusses the physics beyond
physics, that is to say, the science of the not-readily-demonstratable truth.
In Book Alpha of this compound work,
Aristotle dwells on what might constitute a philosophically complete
explanation of causation, and
concludes that with most natural phenomena you have to recognise four different
avenues of causation, as follows .....
"There are four basic ways in which one thing can
cause another. It can be its cause by providing the form that it realises, by
being the matter from which it is made, by being the source of the process that
leads to its coming to be, or by being that for the sake of which the thing is
produced. In any actual case of causal explanation it is vital to distinguish
these four kinds of causation" (Aristotle, ca. 350 BCE, The Metaphysics [Lawson-Tancred
Translation], p11).
In Book Beta,
Aristotle takes these "four causes" and derives no less than 15
"puzzles", which, taken together, delineate the proper scope of
metaphysics. The remainder of the work is then an exploration, with argument
and example versus counter-argument and counter-example, but no final
resolution. Here are the 15 puzzles, as laid out in Lawson-Tancred's (1998)
editorial introduction .....
Puzzle #1:
The question here is whether there is a single science of the aforementioned
four causes, or several such sciences.
Puzzle #2:
The question here is whether the same science covers the studies of logic and
substance.
Puzzle #3:
The question here is whether there is a single science of "sensible"
and "supra-sensible" substances.
Puzzle #4:
The question here is whether the science of substance is also the science of
the properties of substance.
Puzzle #5:
The question here is whether there are only sensible substances or also
supra-sensible ones.
Puzzle #6:
The question here is whether the "principles of entities" consist of
"the material elements of which they are composed or the genera to which
they belong" (p53).
Puzzle #7:
If the answer to Puzzle #6 is "genera", then the further question is
whether we are talking "primary genera" or "ultimate
genera".
Puzzle #8:
The question here is whether there is "something over and above particular
individuals" (p54).
Puzzle #9:
The question here is whether principles have "formal or numerical
unity" (p54).
Puzzle #10:
The question here is whether the principles of perishable and imperishable
things are the same or different.
Puzzle #11:
The question here is whether "one and being" are "per se substances".
Puzzle #12:
The question here is whether numbers, bodies, surfaces, and points are all
substances.
Puzzle #13:
The question here is whether it is necessary to allow Forms in addition to
entities.
Puzzle #14:
The question here is whether principles themselves "have being" as a
potentiality before they appear in actuality.
Puzzle #15:
The question here is whether principles are universal or particular.
Meta-Representation:
[See firstly representation.] A meta-representation is a representation of a
representation. The term comes from Rutgers University's Zenon W. Pylyshyn
(Pylyshyn, 1978), but the underlying principles are also seen in Miller,
Kessel, and Flavell's (1970) notion of the sort of "recursive"
representation needed by people thinking
about people thinking about people, etc. Pylyshyn (1978) offers the
following example statements .....
"I know that snow is white."
"I know that X knows that snow is white."
"I know that X knows that Y knows that snow is
white."
ASIDE: Scott (2006 online)
warns that there is a far-reaching difference of emphasis between these two
definitions. He begins by taking as an example of a first-order belief, the
proposition "Melissa believes that her dog is dead". For this to mean
anything, he argues, requires that two separate mental representations be in
place, namely (a) the substantive proposition "My dog is dead", and
(b) some sort of "true" code. The second-order belief "Anne
believes that Melissa believes that her dog is dead" is admittedly more
complex, and yet despite the fact that it is a second-order belief it does NOT
require a second-order representation to process it. It requires only "a
representation of Melissa's mental state of believing". This implies
(rather counter-intuitively) that Anne will be aware of Melissa's belief while
Melissa herself is not! So it is the "belief states" which present
the processing and storage load, not the representations as such.
To cut a long story short, it appears that
meta-representation is a biologically fragile ability, and can fail, resulting
in impaired social interactions as set out in the entry for mind-reading and the onward links.
Method of Repeated
Production: This is a memory test in which subjects are presented with test stimuli
and required to reproduce them from memory after a series of intervals. Wulf
(1922) used this method to investigate progressive changes in the memory trace
for simple visual shapes, and Bartlett (1932) used it to investigate
progressive changes in memory for narrative. [Compare method of serial
reproduction.]
Method of Savings: This is a powerful
but complex memory measure dating back to Ebbinghaus (1885). The subject is
firstly trained to criterion on the learning task in question. Learning is then
discontinued for a period, as a result of which some forgetting will take
place. At the end of this period, the subject is retrained to the original
criterion. The number of retraining trials, however, is less than it would have
been had there been no initial training (because some learning survived the
delay period). Retraining measures (or "relearning" measures, or "savings") can thus be used to
measure both the amount of initial learning and the speed of its loss.
Method of Serial
Reproduction: This is a memory test in which subjects are presented with test stimuli
and required to reproduce them from memory after an interval. This reproduction
is then used as the test stimulus for a second subject, whose output is used as
the stimulus for the third subject, and so on. Bartlett (1932) used this
method to investigate progressive changes in memory for narrative. [Compare
method of repeated production.]
Metzinger, Thomas: [German philosopher (1958-).] [Home Page] Thomas Metzinger is arguably the most
interdisciplinary mental philosopher since Leibniz,
and speaks with authority not only on matters phenomenological, but also on
just about every other aspect of cognitive science as well.
ASIDE: One can readily list eight supersciences with at
least a passing contribution to make to cognitive science, namely mental
philosophy, cultural anthropology, physical anthropology, zoology,
neuroscience, psychology, computer science, and theoretical linguistics. In
turn, these supersciences have discrete disciplines within them (social versus cognitive versus developmental
psychology, for example). It is therefore a tribute to Metzinger's energy that
the only discipline we see little or no mention of in his writings is computer
science's own private version of epistemology, that is to say, database design.
Meynert,
Theodor Hermann: [Austrian
neurologist (1833-1892).] [Click
for external biography] Meynert graduated as a physician in 1861, and specialised
in psychiatric medicine, being appointed professor of nervous diseases at the
University of Vienna in 1873. He did much to attract up-and-coming
clinician-theorists such as Wernicke
and Freud, and established such an
international reputation that William James
adopted "the Meynert scheme" in his Principles of Psychology (James, 1890, pI.26). Fancher (2002/2006
online) assesses Meynert's importance as follows .....
"According to [Meynert's] model the cortex is the
anatomical substrate of mind, with specific cells in the sensory and motor
areas representing specific ideas and memories. The specific cells are
potentially interconnected in a vast network by means of 'association fibres,'
the bulk of whose substance lies in the frontal lobes. After two cells have
been simultaneously excited (equivalent to the simultaneous arousal or two
ideas), an association fibre opens up between them. With each subsequent
simultaneou excitation, it opens up further. This provides the anatomical basis
for the association of ideas; after an association fibre has opened up it
provides a pathway by which excitation in one center can flow directly to the
other. A 'train of thought' is simply the consequence of excitation flowing
through a series of cortical cells that have been associated because of
previous simultaneous excitations. Every person, of course, has a unique
pattern of experience and so develops a unique pattern of cortical associations
that represent his memories. These associations are the anatomical substrate of
a person's 'individuality,' and Meynert referred to them collectively as the ego
(German Ich)" (Fancher, 2002/2006
online).
Michotte,
Albert: [Belgian psychologist
(1881-1965).] [Click
for external biography] See causality.
Mill, James: [British Associationist
philosopher (1773-1836).] [Click
for external biography] See Associationism.
Mill, John
Stuart:
[British Utilitarianist philosopher (1806-1873).] [Click for external
biography] See ratiocination.
Mill, Leibniz's: See Leibniz's
mill.
Miller, Neal E.: [American
psychologist (1909-2002).] [Click
for external biography] Miller is noteworthy in the context of the present
glossary for his work on aggression,
frustration and, as well as for more or less single-handedly constructing
the science of biofeedback.
Miller,
George A.: [American psychologist
(1920-).] [Click for external biography]
Miller [academic homepage] is
noteworthy in the context of the present glossary for having established the
cognitivist perspective with his 1955 paper "The Magical Number Seven" (Miller, 1956). [See also chunking.]
Mimesis: [(Adjectival form "mimetic") Greek <μιμησις>
(now acceptable as technical English) = "imitation".] See image.
Mimema[ta]: [Greek = "the thing[s] imitated" (from mimesis).]
[See firstly image.] A mimema is "the result of an activity
[the Greeks] named mimesis"
(Sörbom, 2002/2006
online). Mimemata are things to be perceived, but not real ones. Mimemata
thus include, but are not limited to, pictorial representations. Here is how
Sörbom (2002/2006 online) explains this at-first-sight confusing distinction .....
"When the Greeks of the classical period wanted
to characterise the basic nature of painting and sculpture, poetry and music,
dance and theatre, i.e., things we today call works of art, most of them agreed
that such things were mimemata
[.....], the result of an activity they named mimesis. [.....] Traditionally the English word 'imitation' is
used, although inadequately, to translate the Greek word mimesis and the philosophical discussion of the behaviour denoted
by mimesis is commonly called 'the theory of
imitation'. [..... However,] several words were used more or less synonymously
as, for instance, mimema (imitation),
eikon (image), homoioma (likeness)" (Sörbom, 2002/2006
online).
"The basic distinction for the ancient theory of mimesis was that between mimemata and real things. For example, a
house is a real thing whereas a painting or a sculpture representing a house is
a mimema, a thing which looks like a
house but is not a house. [.....] The mimema
as a thing is a sort of vehicle for 'man-made dreams produced for those who are
awake', as Plato suggestively formulates it (Sophist, 266c). Neither the dream nor the mimema is a real thing" (ibid.).
Mind:
In everyday usage, one's
"mind" is "the seat of a person's consciousness, thoughts,
volitions, and feelings; the system of cognitive and emotional phenomena and
powers that constitutes the subjective being of a person" (O.E.D.). This definition
fits well with Descartes' (1642) observation that mind was "that substance
in which thought immediately resides" (Descartes, Objections and Replies, §161/6; Haldane and Ross translation,
p254), but it lacks scientific precision [because if we go on to ask what
"thought" is, we reply - too circularly for comfort - that it is what the mind "does"].
The word itself comes from the Latin mens via its inflected form mentis,
and is theoretically useful to the extent that it brings together into a single
lexeme all facets of mental function [the Greek philosophers had used the
separate terms nous, oiesis, psuche,
etc., to chart much the same territory; the Germans Gemüt, Sinn,
Kopf, Geist, Seele, etc.]. Mediaeval and
Renaissance Western philosophers tended (if they knew what was good for them)
to follow the church's official line, that is to say, they adopted St. Thomas
Aquinas's Vatican-approved form of the Greek writings. The 17th century then
divided its effort between the Aristotelianism of the British Empiricists and the Platonism of the Continental Rationalists [see the separate entries for the
details]. John Locke, for example, expressed the Empiricist position on
mind, as follows .....
"'Clear and distinct ideas' are terms which,
though familiar and frequent in men's mouths, I have reason to think every one
who uses does not perfectly understand. [.....] I have therefore, in most
places, chose to put 'determinate' ir 'determined', instead of 'clear' and 'distinct'
[.....]. By these denominations, I mean some object in the mind, and consequently determined, i.e., such as it is
there seen and perceived to be" (Locke, nominally 1690, prefatory notes to
the sixth edition of On the Human Understanding [Sir John Lubbock
Edition], xv).
..... whereas the Rationalist
Gottfried Leibniz saw it as the faculty to reason with the material
available to it, expressing himself thus in this scholarly response to Locke
.....
"From this it appears that necessary truths, such
as we find in pure mathematics and particularly in arithmetic and geometry,
must have principles whose proof does not depend on instances nor,
consequently, on the testimony of the senses, even though without the senses it
would never occur to us to think of them. [.....] Logic also abounds in such
truths [.....] and so the proof of them can only come from inner principles,
which are described as innate. It would indeed be wrong to think that we can
easily read these eternal laws of reason in the soul [.....] but it is enough that they can be discovered
within us by dint of attention: the senses give the occasion, and the results
of experiments also serve to corroborate reason, somewhat as checks in
arithmetic help us to avoid errors of calculation in long chains of reasoning.
While men are capable of demonstrative knowledge, beasts, so far as one can
judge, never manage to form necessary propositions, since the faculty by which
they make thought sequences is something lower than the reason that occurs in men.
Beasts' thought sequences are just like those of simple empirics who maintain
that what has happened once will happen again in [similar circumstances],
although that does not enable them to judge whether the same reasons are at
work. [.....] The thought sequences of beasts are only a shadow of reasoning,
that is, they are nothing but a connection in the imagination - a passage from
one image to another. [.....] For only reason is capable of establishing reliable rules"
(Leibniz, 1704/1764, New Essays on the Human Understanding [Remnant and Bennett (1996) edition],
§§50-51).
The Empiricist-Rationalist stand-off continued until
Immanuel Kant led a late-18th
century drive for a compromise "Positivist"
position, in which both Locke and Leibniz were equally taken to task for
telling less than the whole story. For Kant, the mind both received sensations
and then experienced as a result "pure intuitions", and
could use both as material of and for reasoning, thus [a long extract,
heavily abridged] .....
"The effect of an object on our capacity for
presentation, insofar as we are affected by the object, is sensation. Intuition that refers to the object through sensation is
called empirical intuition. The
undetermined object of an empirical intuition is called appearance. [.....] All presentations in which nothing is found
that belongs to sensation I call pure (in the transcendental sense of the
term). Accordingly, the pure form of sensible intuitions generally [..... is
called] pure intuition. Thus, if from
the presentation of a body I separate what the understanding thinks in it
[.....] I am still left with something from this empirical intuition, namely
extension and shape. [.....] There must, therefore, be a science of [.....] transcendental aesthetic [..... in
which] we shall, first of all, isolate
sensibility, by separating from it everything that the understanding through
its concepts thinks (in connection) with it, so that nothing other than
empirical intuition will remain. Second, we shall also segregate from sensibility everything that
belongs to sensation, so that nothing will remain but pure intuition [..... of]
space and time" (Kant,
1781/1789, Critique [Pluhar Translation], pp72-75; bold emphasis added).
For our own part, we like the mid-19th century stance
taken by James Mill in his "Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human
Mind" (Mill, 1869), in that (despite its very clear title) this work has
no chapter (nor, indeed, lesser section) devoted to the mind. Instead, the word
"mind" is used to give a one-syllable handle onto a range of lesser
aspects of mentation, and you are required to focus from the outset on the various
outward displays of mind, not the thing itself,
"observing them one at a time with sufficient care", deriving
"empirical generalisations of limited compass, but of great value for
practice", and very carefully noting (and learning from) those occasions
when these generalisations fail, due to our lack of understanding, to fit
together (op. cit., vii). Mill takes account of Locke's
sensations and ideas as one major subset of these phenomena, but then includes
chapters in turn on "consciousness", "imagination",
"abstraction", "belief", "ratiocination" [=
"reasoning"], and "the will". This was also the era in
which three new branches of psychological science emerged more or less
simultaneously, as follows .....
1. Neuropsychology: This line of enquiry studies the effects of brain injury or disease
upon the various phenomena of mind - see the companion resource
for an introductory timeline [start at Broca (1861) for the short form of the
story].
2. Clinical Psychology: This line of enquiry reflects a sudden fascination
with what went on in the world's lunatic asylums - see the entry for hysteria
for some illustrative detail.
3. The Unconscious: See the entry for unconscious, the for some illustrative detail.
When we get to the 20th century the situation becomes
even more complicated, because we have by then started to treat theoretical
mental philosophy as "philosophy", and experimental mental philosophy
as "psychology". On the philosophical side of things, the British,
increasingly represented by Bertrand Russell, followed Mill [see, for example,
Russell's (1921) The Analysis of Mind], the Germans followed Kant's
phenomenological tradition via Husserl
and Meinong to Heidegger, and the Americans toyed with the Pragmatism of the Chicago
School. With psychology as experimental science, the British gathered
around Myers and later Bartlett at Cambridge and concentrated
on applied psychology, the Germans gave us the Gestalt School, and the
Americans entered their "Behaviourist period". Then, in the 1950s,
came the so-called "cognitive revolution" [nicely reviewed in 2003 by
Princeton's revolutionary-in-chief, George A. Miller - see Miller (2003/2007 online)],
although it would still be another two decades before a flurry of works agreed
that the mind had been regained as a topic of study, and that the
"psych" was back in psychology.
ASIDE: Interested readers could do a lot worse than begin
with Holt's (1964) "The Return of the Ostracised", in which he charted the
return of imagery, move on to Joynson's
(1972) "The Return of Mind", and then follow up with Howard Gardner's
"The Quest for Mind" (Gardner, 1973), Colin Blakemore's
"Mechanics of the Mind" (Blakemore, 1977), and later works such as
Richard Gregory's "Mind in Science" (Gregory, 1981), Marvin Minsky's
"The Society of Mind" (Minsky, 1985), and Gardner's own follow-up
work, "The Mind's New Science" (Gardner, 1985).
Modern research has added at least three major new
avenues of enquiry into mind, as follows [numbering continues from the previous
indent, to indicate that these are additional, not replacement, areas of
interest] .....
4.
Artificial Intelligence Studies: This
line of enquiry studies machine simulations of such cognitive phenomena as
translation, semantics, gaming, machine learning and problem-solving, robotics,
and artificial consciousness, and dates from the birth of the electronic
computer in the late 1940s. We have covered it in considerable detail elsewhere
[for the early years, see Section 4 of "Short-Term
Memory (Part 4)", and for the more recent years see Section 1.10 to
1.13 and 3.5 to 3.13 of "Short-Term
Memory (Part 5)"].
5.
Functional Neuroimaging: This line of
enquiry studies the correlations between more-or-less controlled mental
activity and more-or-less externally detectable brain activity. It came
on-stream in the 1980s with the PET and rCBF techniques of functional
tomography, and has improved in resolution, both spatial and temporal, ever
since. The modern method of choice is fMRI [click
for technical details].
6. "Cognitive
Palaeontology": This line of
argument attempts to reverse engineer the belief systems of extinct hominids
from the physically more enduring data to be found in the fossil record.
Schmidt (1934/1936) showed what could be achieved here [see the mention in the entry for identity, comparative approaches to], but we shall provisionally date
the modern science to Etienne Patté's (1960) "Les Hommes Préhistoriques et la Religion", although it was
later works such as Mithen's (1996) "The Prehistory of the Mind"
which have really popularised the new science.
[See now mind-brain
problem.]
Mindblindness:
This is Baron-Cohen's (1997) term for
a defect in an individual's powers of mental modelling specifically for the
minds (and needs etc.) of other people, which single defect, as such, is seen
as constituting the root cause of all three facets of Wing's triad on all autistic
spectrum disorders. Mindblindness is thus one of the best available
examples of the cognitive deficit
approach to the understanding of mental abnormality, and it achieves its often
devastating pathological effect from the fact that it disrupts our species'
ability for mind-reading. In short,
it impairs our social understanding. [For the more detailed history of this
topic, see theory of mind theory of
autism.]
Mind-Brain Debate:
"Is [death] not just the separation
of soul and body?"
(Plato, Phaedo, §64c; Jowett translation, p112).
[See firstly soul,
tripartite.] This is the name given to the confrontation between those who
believe mind and soul are two different things and those
who believe they ultimately share an explanation (and a host of positions in
between). The fundamental issue is whether that which we experience at first
hand as the workings of our mind (i.e. our perceptions, emotions, memories,
insights, etc.) might conceivably be supported by the "two fistfuls of
porridge" (Taylor, 1991) which is our brain. The problems are then (a)
that we do not have experiential access to most of what goes on in our mind (to
borrow one useful current phrase, most of that lower activity is
"transparent" to our introspections), (b) that even when
introspection is successful it is by definition impossible for it to be independently
validated, and (c) that we are not yet good enough engineers to fathom out the
brain's operating principles [that which James Clerk Maxwell in the 19th
century and Kenneth Craik in the 20th liked to call "the 'go' of it"
(Sherwood, 1966)]. Or to put it another way, there is a lot of mind which never
experiences anything, but just goes happily about its work. As a result, there
have always been fundamentally different competing views on the mind-brain
relationship, as introduced by the separate entry for dualisms or monisms. Russell (1921) offers a concise definition, thus .....
"Those who maintain that mind is
the reality and matter an evil dream are called 'idealists' [.....]. Those who
argue that matter is the reality and mind a mere property of protoplasm are
called 'materialists'. [..... Unfortunately,] the stuff of which the world of
our experience is composed is, in my belief, neither mind nor matter, but
something more primitive than either" (p10).
Mindfulness: This is Kabat-Zinn's (1990) term for the continuum
of self knowledge and control along which individuals can improve once they
have learned (if necessary under the guidance of a psychotherapist) to support
their awareness of their own mental processes with an appropriate package of
attentional control skills. Kabat-Zinn marketed the construct and his
particular package of "mindfulness training" techniques as the Mindfulness-Based
Stress Reduction regime, a subvariant form of cognitive behavioural
therapy.
Mindfulness-Based Stress Reduction (MBSR): This is Kabat-Zinn's (1990/2003) variant form of mindfulness training
(itself a subvariant of cognitive behavioural therapy). It is "an
eight-session course that teaches participants to become more aware of their
mental processes and to develop attentional control" (Smith, 2004,
p423).
Mindfulness Training (MT): [See firstly mindfulness.] This is the generic term for modern
psychotherapeutic systems based on the construct of mindfulness [see, for
example, mindfulness-based cognitive
therapy and mindfulness-based stress
reduction]. Smith (2004) highlights MT's core clinical strategies this way .....
"Superficially, MT may seem to conflict with CBT.
Metacognitive theory seems to suggest that because people with emotional disorders
self-focus a great deal and this worsens their distress, MT might make matters
worse. In fact, many people self-focus in unhelpful ways (self-critically, or
persistently trying to solve the insoluble) when emotionally distressed, and MT
helps them to become aware of this, helping them to disengage from
self-focusing and to alter how they self-focus towards acceptance and kindness
rather than self-criticism and rumination. Another apparent tension between MT
and CBT is that in cognitive therapy clients learn how to 'fix' things (e.g.,
to modify 'automatic thoughts). In MT there is no 'fixing', rather they are
simply taught to become aware of such thoughts, neither trying to change them
nor act on them" (p424).
Mindness: This
is Llinás' (1987) notion of a "high-level awareness, including
self-awareness" (p356) which allows "complex goal-directed
interactions between a living organism and its environment" (p339). [See
now how Llinás uses mindness in defending his own brand of physicalism.]
Mind-Reading:
This is Humphrey's (1984) term for socially
directed cognition, that is to say, cognition which is in some way
responsive to the mental states of others, and which is capable, consequently, of
using that information to plan more effective interactions with those others.
Mind-reading skills, in other words, help you get your own way! Mind-reading is
a powerful and far-reaching cognitive skill, as the following scenarios will demonstrate .....
(1) You give a gesture of encouragement to a harassed
colleague at a particularly stressful business meeting, because you know what
they are thinking and are sympathetic to what they are feeling. Why? Team spirit, perhaps; or because that colleague is your only
supporter in a forthcoming issue of contention.
(2) You shortly need to borrow your neighbour's
lawnmower, but remember that you still have to return the ladder he lent you
the other week. You therefore make a point of expansively returning the ladder,
complete with a posy of flowers for his wife.
In each of these scenarios, there is a central and
critical cognitive requirement, namely that you should have room enough in your
personal mental model of the world
not just for other people as tangible things but for their mental states as well! As to the necessary
mechanisms, Whiten (1996) warns very forcefully that mind-reading "is not
telepathy" (p277), but depends rather on a complex mix of observations
of another's behaviour in a prevailing context. Moreover, the mechanisms responsible - whatever they eventually turn
out to be - need to be available to animals and non-verbal humans, and should
not therefore be overspecified! [See now theory of mind.]
"Mind
Stuff": See res cogitans.
Mind
Within Mind: See consciousness, Dennett's theory of and the entry for inner speech.
Mine-ness: This is one of the three
philosophically interesting aspects of the first-person perspective identified by Metzinger
(2003, 2005b) (the others being selfhood and perspectivalness). Metzinger uses the term to refer to the
phenomenological aspects of internality, that is to say, to "the
consciously experienced quality of 'inwardness' accompanying bodily
sensations" (Metzinger, 2003, p267), and sees it as requiring a
"prereflexive sense of ownership" (ibid.), and as manifesting itself "continuously,
automatically, and independently of any high-level cognitive operations" (ibid.).
Mini Mental State
Examination (MMSE): The MMSE is a quick bedside screening test for higher
cognitive functions. For details of questions and scoring, click
here. Note the ten short questions addressing orientation to time and
place.
Minimum Stimulus
Current: In the context of neurotransmission, this is the smallest
continuous stimulation required to exceed the action potential threshold.
Minute
Perceptions: ["Minute" as
in "small". See firstly aesthesis,
phenomenal awareness, and ideation.] This (more strictly its French
equivalent, petites perceptions) is Leibniz's (1704/1765, New Essays on the Human Understanding)
term for a grade of perceptual content part-way between the full phenomenal
awareness of something [a state he referred to as "apperception"] and the raw sensory input. New
Essays was prepared in the period 1703 to 1704 as a corrective response to
the first (in 1700) French translation of Locke's (1690) Essays Concerning the Human Understanding,
but its publication was delayed because no sooner had it been completed than
Locke died. Only some time after Leibniz's own death (in 1716) did scholars
collate and release the manuscript (in 1765). Later scholars have retranslated
and re-edited the work. Here, from the
1951 Wiener edition is Leibniz's introduction of the target term [which he
invoked in the context of a broader discussion of the relationship between
perception and consciousness] .....
"Furthermore, there are
a thousand indications which lead us to think that there are at every moment
numberless perceptions in us, but
without apperception and without reflection; that is to say, changes in the
soul itself of which we are not conscious, because the impressions are either
too slight or in too great a number or too even, so that they have nothing to
distinguish them one from the other; but joined to others, they do not fail to
produce their effect and to make themselves felt at least confusedly in the mass.
Thus it is that custom causes us not to take notice of the motion of a mill
or of a waterfall when we have lived near them for some time. It is not that
the motion does not always strike our organs, and that something does not enter
the soul which responds to it [.....]; but these impressions [.....], being destitute of the charms of novelty, are not strong enough to attract our attention and
our memory, attached as they are to objects more engrossing. For all attention requires
memory, [..... even when] we let [present perceptions] pass without reflection
and even without being noticed; but if some one calls our attention to them
immediately afterwards and makes us notice, for example, some noise which was
just heard, we remember it and are conscious of having had at the time some
feeling of it. Thus they
were perceptions of which we were not immediately conscious, apperception only coming
in this case from the warning received after some interval, small though it may
be. And to judge still better of the minute perceptions which we are unable to
distinguish in the crowd, I am accustomed to make use of the example of the
roar or noise of the sea which strikes one when on the shore. To hear this
noise as one does it would be necessary to hear the parts which compose the
whole, that is to say, the noise of each wave, although each of these little
noises only makes itself known in the confused collection of all the others
together, that is to say, in the roar itself, and would not be noticed if the
wave which makes it was alone"
(Leibniz, 1704/1764, New Essays on
the Human Understanding [Wiener
edition, 1951, pp374-375], §53-54;
bold emphasis added); the more complete
Remnant and Bennett (1996) translation maintains the above sense].
ASIDE: Note the above reference to
mills, an allusion which Leibniz went on to repeat in his 1714 Monadology
[see the entry for Leibniz's
mill]. It
may or may not be relevant that the author had spent some time around 1679 as
consultant mining engineer to Duke Johann Friedrich of Brunswick, during which
period he experimented with a mine drainage pumping system powered by
windmills.
It is worth noting, in
passing, that Leibniz had already observed 20 years earlier that the roar of
the sea was a complex perception built out of an accumulation of simpler
perceptions. Here is how he described this phenomenon in his Discourse on Metaphysics .....
"We can also see that
the perceptions of our senses, even when clear, must necessarily contain some
confused feeling. For [our body] receives the impressions of all the others,
and although our senses bear relations to everything, it is not possible for
our soul to attend to everything in all of its particulars. Thus our
confused feelings are the result of a variety of perceptions which is indeed
infinite - very like the confused murmur a person hears when approaching the
sea-shore, which comes from the putting together of the reverberations of
innumerable waves. For if several perceptions do not come together to make one, and there
is no one which stands out above all the others, and if they all make
impressions which are more or less equally strong and equally capable of
catching its attention, the soul can only perceive them confusedly"
(Leibniz, 1686, Discourse on Metaphysics [Woolhouse and Francks (1998)
edition, pp85-86], §33; bold emphasis
added).
Returning to New Essays,
Leibniz continues .....
"These minutes (petites) perceptions are then
of greater influence because of their consequences than is thought. It is they
which form I know not what, these tastes, these images
of the sensible qualities, clear in the mass but confused in the parts, these
impressions which surrounding bodies make upon us, [etc.]. It may even be said
that in consequence of these minute perceptions the present is big with the
future and laden with the past [..... They] indicate also and constitute
the identity of the individual, who is characterised by the traces or expressions
which they preserve of the preceding states of this individual, in making the
connection with his present state" (Leibniz, 1704/1764, New Essays on the Human Understanding [Wiener edition, 1951, p376], §55; bold emphasis added).
WHERE TO NEXT:
Gennaro (1999/2007
online) has recently revisited Leibniz's mental philosophy, noting that
minute perceptions allow "mentality" without consciousness, and then incorporating
this notion into the modern debate over higher-order thought. Leibniz thus deserves to be included in any history
of the unconscious. As for the
closing remark about minute perceptions being involved in the machinery of
human identity, it is possible that Leibniz was here following the same train
of thought as Husserl had been with his notion of marginal
co-data. This possibility is
further discussed in the entry for identity,
Leibniz's approach to.
Mirror Neuron: [See firstly action schema and mental model.]
This is Rizzolatti et al's (various from 1996) notion of a localised neural
system which is selectively responsive to commonalities of behaviour between a
host animal and other animals (or objects) in that host animal's perceptual
environment. Such neural systems were first identified by implanted electrode
recording from the brains of macaque monkeys, but have now been tentatively
located non-invasively in humans as well [see Winerman (2005/2007 online) for a
review of the methodologies]. For the brain to behave in this way, there has to be some sort of overlap between the neural
subsystem for one's personal action schemas and the subsystem for coding the
behaviour of others in our mental model of the world. Hurley (e.g., 2005)
refers to the extent of this putative overlap as a "shared circuit".
Mirror Self-Recognition Test: [See firstly efference
copy and reafference.] This is a simple test paradigm devised by
Gallup (1970), and much used since. In the simplest form of the paradigm, a
sleeping subject (adult, child, animal) is marked on
the face with a spot of coloured paint and then its behaviour closely observed
when exposed to a mirror upon awakening. The received argument is that if the
subject touches the spot on its actual face when seeing its reflected
face, it must (a) know where in space parts of its body it has never directly seen are, (b) know that the image it is
looking at is a mimetic first-person (i.e., a mirror-image of itself) rather
than a substantive second-person (i.e., an actual other), and (c) know how to
plan and execute smooth hand and arm movements, where the visual efference copy
and reafference aspects of the processing will need to be duly mirror-inverted.
Mitochondrion: (Pl:
Mitochondria.) This is a sausage-shaped organelle of which several
hundred may be present in a given cell. It acts as the cell's
"powerhouse", that is to say, it is where the energy source adenosine
triphosphate (ATP) is stored pending demand.
MMSE: See Mini Mental
State Examination.
Mnemonic: In both everyday
and technical English, a "mnemonic" is an encoding strategy
for enhancing memory performance.
Modal Model of
Memory (MMM): A consensus (hence "modal") approach to memory theory which
emerged during the 1960s, and which was most clearly expounded by Atkinson and
Shiffrin (1971). The MMM treats memory phenomena as beginning
with sensory memory, advancing to STM, and consolidating to LTM,
and as being supported along the way by such processes as rehearsal and encoding.
The approach eventually lost popularity in the mid-1970s, due to competition
from Working Memory Theory.
Mode
(1/2): (1) [See firstly idea,
complex.] Within mental philosophy, a mode is one of Locke's three
subclasses of complex idea (the others being substance and relation),
thus: "'Modes' I call such complex ideas which, however compounded,
contain not in them the supposition of subsisting by themselves, but are
considered as dependences on or affections of substances; such are the ideas
signified by the words 'triangle, gratitude, murder', etc." (Locke, 1690, p109). (2)
Within engineering design, a mode is one of several optional ways of functioning in a system where relative structural simplicity has been
achieved by designing apart the required functional complexity into distinct
applications, mapped separately into the hardware. Such systems thus have a
number of "modes" of operation, each dealing
with a particular functional application. The resulting structural simplicity
brings size and cost benefits, but there is a trade-off cost in terms of longer
familiarisation periods and reduced ease of control. Modes of this sort are not
new. One everyday example is that of the shift
key on the modern computer keyboard, an arrangement inherited from late
19th century typewriters in which a mode selection toggle-key is used to switch
the main key array from lower case mode TO UPPER CASE MODE and BACK again ON
dEmAnD.
WHERE TO NEXT:
Mode theory acquires perhaps its greatest practical relevance when particular
designs push operator skills to their limits. It is regularly invoked, for
example, in the literature on forensic ergonomics - the science of avoidable
disasters- as detailed in the entry for mode
error.
Mode
Error: [See firstly mode (2).] In
the context of the forensic ergonomics of avoidable disasters, the term
"mode error" refers to a mismatch between the actual mode setting on
a control system and that of the mental
model of said system in the mind of its present operator(s). This is the
situation in which the operators believe the system is in one mode, and
therefore responding in one particular way, when in fact it is in a different
mode. In such circumstances as these, the system is not just effectively
disconnected from its controls, but will remain so unless and until the
operator(s) eventually realise what is going on - if, indeed, their error does
not kill them first .....
EXAMPLES: Here is an example
of the present authoR CONTINUING TO TYPE IN LOWERCASE WHILE HIS HARDWARE HAD
ACCIDENTALLY SWITCHED ITSELF INTO UPPER CASE MODE. An error of scarcely greater complexity caused the Air Inter air disaster, Strasbourg, France, in 1992, in which 87
people died [see case, Strasbourg A320
Air Disaster, 1992 for details].
Mode error of this sort is a
major risk in modern highly computerised control systems, and its avoidance in
a major design problem for the design engineers and cognitive ergonomists
involved.
Modified
Card Sorting Test (MCST): See Wisconsin Card Sorting Test.
Modularity:
Modular processing is a system design
philosophy which insists that the best way to cope with unavoidable complexity
is for like to be located with like. Where the system in question is an
information processing system, the modularity philosophy needs to be applied
both to the content and its processing. Metaphorically speaking, for
example, there would be "modularity of content" in a university which
had its science library on a different campus to its humanities library, and
there would be "modularity of processing" in a library which had one
clerk trained up for cataloguing accessions and another for supporting
literature searching. In the computer industry, processing is invariably less
troublesome when it is separated into functionally dedicated clusters, or
"modules", each capable of operating more or less in isolation.
Modularity is relevant in the current context, because it is a common belief
that similar considerations apply to cognitive science, where the computer in
question is the nervous system. Jerry Fodor - one of the main theorists on this
issue - defines a module as an "'informationally
encapsulated' cognitive facility" (Fodor, 1987, p25) [readers
unfamiliar with this term should spend five minutes on the separate entry
before proceeding]. As demonstrated in any of the large psycholinguistic models
[show me one],
there is a significant amount of modularity in the human communication system,
and it is the vulnerability of these modules to partial damage which causes
clinical communication syndromes to occur in such amazing variety. Shanon
(1988) reviewed the three key elements of the Fodorian module, namely
domain-specificity, limited central access, and informational encapsulation,
and although he is generally sympathetic to the Fodorian notion that perceptual
systems fit this description whilst central systems do not, he notes, even so,
that there are exceptions both ways. With central processing, for example, he
notes a degree of modularity where there should be none. Thus
.....
"At first blush it seems that it makes no sense
to speak of modularity in the central processes. Fodor gives enough good
functional reasons why processes should be nondenominational and unencapsulated.
[..... Yet that] characterisation of central modularity is based on
considerations of principle and follows a perspective which may be
characterised as philosophical rather than psychological. [.....] Specifically,
the respect by which the said properties apply to the system may be
context-dependent, and the system may thus exhibit patterns of local
modularity [note this term - Ed.]. It is here that the contrast between the
philosophical and psychological perspective is apparent. Whereas for Fodor
informational encapsulation that is context-dependent and varies with time is
demonstrative of non-modularity [.....], the perpective proposed here suggests,
by contrast, that it be taken as indicative of possible modularity [.....].
This I say not because I deny the patterns of non-modularity, but because what
I deem important is the dynamics of mind, and this dynamics consists, inter
alia, of the changing of the boundaries of modularity [see sidenote below]
Thus, in proposing the attribution of modularity to central processes I am not
arguing against the (probably true) claim that anything can, in principle, be
made unencapsulated. Rather, I propose to change perspective and instead of
looking at the ever-present possibility of non-encapsulation consider the
actual and potential patterns of encapsulation" (Shanon, 1988, pp340-341;
emphasis added).
In Shanon's subsequent discussion of domain
specificity and informational encapsulation he notes a number of central
"mental islands" (p342), such as prejudices in the attitudinal
system, the object-specific response tendencies discussed in such great detail
by object-relations theorists, and even the "segregation of the split
personality" (p343). He concludes as follows .....
"By way of exemplifying the rigidity of Fodor's
perspective let me note his likening of the central system of the mind to a
Sears catalog [an indexed body of detail - Ed.], hence his appraisal that it is
not worthy of scientific investigation. Fodor searches for well-defined
structures and when he does not discover them he concludes that there is only
one big mess. Yet between fixed nicely formalisable structures and a Sears
catalog (assuming for the sake of discussion that it is a total mess, which in
all likelihood it is not) there are intermediate states of affairs"
(Shanon, 1988, p348).
ASIDE: Note Shanon's observation that there is probably more
to the nature of an indexed set of entities than might at first glance meet the
eye, and then see the entry for database.
Note also the issue of the "boundaries of modularity" changing
dynamically, because this is precisely the sort of momentary reorganisation of
resources suggested by Calvin (1983) in his analysis of throwing accuracy - see
the companion précis
for details.
For their part, Marslen-Wilson and Tyler (1987) have
analysed the modularity of human language processing, where Fodorian modules
abound everywhere other than in the central semantic system [see, for example, Ellis (1982), Ellis and Young
(1988), Kay,
Lesser and Coltheart (1992), and Coltheart,
Curtis, Atkins, and Haller (1993)]. However, like Shanon, they are
concerned that the modularity hypothesis "gives the wrong kind of
account" (p37) of language processing, because the boundaries of its known
components "do not neatly coincide" (ibid.). One of the big
mysteries, for example, is the sheer speed with which the final "interpreted
meaning" (p38) of a given input is computed. The possible explanation,
they submit, is that the admittedly modular input systems "encroach"
into "processing territories reserved for central processes" (p38).
They critically examined Fodor's criteria of modularity and report weaknesses
in each, before concluding as follows .....
"The facts of psycholinguistic performance simply
do not support the rigid dichotomy between the domains of the syntactic and the
non-syntactic that is the central claim of the modularity thesis. The thesis is
seductive, entertaining, perhaps even heuristically
useful. But as a basis for the construction of explanatory theories of human
psycholinguistic performance it is, we believe, fundamentally misleading. It
misconstrues the nature of the problem that is set for us by the extraordinary
speed and immediacy of on-line language comprehension, and it invites us to
accept, as a solution to this problem, a view of the organisation of the
language-processing system that obscures rather than clarifies the questions we
now need to be asking" (Marslen-Wilson and Tyler, 1987, pp61-62).
[See now massive
modularity. BREAKING RESEARCH: For more on the potential role of "abnormal connectivity" in
preventing or degrading the maximal integration of multi-modular cognitive
processing, see also functional
connectivity and its onward links.]
Molyneux
Question:
In one of the most famous thought experiments of all time, one William Molyneux, asked the
British
Empiricist
philosopher John Locke about the perceptual abilities of a blind man
suddenly made able to see. The specific question was whether that blind man
would be able, using his new but inexperienced sense of sight alone, to
tell a sphere from a cube in a confrontational naming task. But this is such a long
story that we have placed it in a separate file, so if you want to know the
answer, you'll have to click here.
Monad: In archaic erudite English, a "monad" is
"(1) the number one, unity" (O.E.D.). The word was therefore a
natural choice for any philosopher theorising about an ultimate structure for
matter, and in this more specific sense it has been defined as "(2) An
ultimate unit of being; an absolutely simple entity. Chiefly used with
reference to the philosophy of Leibniz" (ibid.). Leibniz used the
word in his 1686 Discourse on Metaphysics when attempting to explain
"the great mystery of the union of the soul and the body" [see the
entry for incarnation], but reserved
his most sustained analysis for his 1714 Monadology. He began with a basic definition, as follows
.....
"The monad, of which we will be speaking
here, is nothing but a simple substance, which enters into composites, simple,
meaning without parts. And there must be simple substances, because there are
composites; for the composite is nothing but a collection of, or aggregatum,
of simples. Now, in that which has no parts, neither
extension, nor shape, nor divisibility is possible. And so monads are the true
atoms of nature; in a word, the elements of things" (Leibniz, 1714, Monadology [Woolhouse
and Francks (1998) Edition, p268], §1-3).
He went on to argue that monads have qualities (§8)
[compare entity and attribute], are by definition different from
each other (§9), and
can exist in different states (§13). He
then, less safely in our opinion, argued that state changes involved processes
of "perception" and "appetition", by virtue of which he was
able, famously, to declared that the human soul was itself a form of monad (§19), to be distinguished from lesser
animate and inanimate monads only by the quality of its memories and its
reasonings (§§20-37). He then diverted to
theological issues for a number of paragraphs (§§38-62), before concluding as follows .....
"The body belonging to a monad, which is either
its entelechy or its soul, makes up together with an entelechy what we can call
a living thing, and together with a soul what we call an animal. Now that body
of a living thing or animal is always organic, because [.....]. Thus every
organic body of a living being is a kind of divine machine or natural
automaton, which infinitely surpasses any artificial automaton, because a
man-made machine is not a machine in every one of its parts. [.....] But
nature's machines - living bodies, that is - are machines even in their
smallest parts, right down to infinity. [.....] And we can see from this that
there is a world of creatures - of living things and animals, entelechies, and
souls - in the smallest part of matter"
(op.cit., p277, §63-65).
[For a fuller introduction to this topic, see §56 of
Weber's History of Philosophy (Weber, 1908/2007
online, courtesy of the University of Idaho). See also and compare entelechy.]
Monism: [See firstly dualisms
or monisms.] A "monism" is
a "one-truth" theoretical position in the mind-brain debate, that is
to say, one which claims that the laws of the mind
and the laws of the brain are fundamentally one and the same. There are a number of discrete sub-orientations
under this heading, claiming either (a) that the laws of the mind are the only
real truth (in which case your monism is an idealism), or (b) that the laws of your brain are the only real
truth (in which case your monism is a physicalism),
or (c) that we are really not too sure (in which case you are probably going to
be a monist one day, but are either an epiphenomenalist,
identity theorist, or emergentist, for the time being).
William James brought the dualism debate centre stage by referring very
disparagingly to "mind stuff" theory, which he characterized as
theories that mental states "are composite in structure, made up of
smaller states conjoined" (James, 1890, pI.145). Llinás (1987) makes much
the same point this way .....
"I for one, as a monist, consider 'mindness' to
be but one of several global physiological computational states that the brain
can generate. An example of another global physiological state, in which
'mindness' is not apparent, is that known as 'being asleep' and yet another is
known as dreaming [.....] Among the above, the 'mindness
state' allows complex goal-directed interactions between a living organism and
its environment" (Llinás, 1987, p339).
More recently, Velmans (2005) has referred to all the
two-stuff theories as "substance dualism" because they are constantly
pitting "material stuff" against "soul or spirit" stuff.
Mood:
In everyday English, mood is "a
frame of mind or state of feelings; one's humour, temper, or disposition at a
particular time" (O.E.D.). In psychology the same basic definition
applies, only there is then a much greater emphasis on the role of mood in
reflecting what goes on at the interface of our emotional and intellectual
selves. As such, mood is the
primary diagnostic variable for an entire cluster of mental health disorders. It is also (like mania) a major source of
theoretical insight to those interested in more philosophical issues such as
the mind-brain problem. Clinically,
a patient's mood is a sign used in the differential diagnosis of-and-within the
various mood disorders
recognised by the DSM-IV. As for the underlying theory, Bollas (1987) relates
moods back to his theory of the transformational object, as follows .....
"In brief, moods are psychic phenomena which
serve important unconscious functions. Like the dream, a mood has a kind of
necessary autistic structure to it: people who are in a mood, like persons who
are asleep, are inside a special state where a temporal element is at play.
They will emerge, like the dreamer, after the spell is over. Some moods,
particularly those that form part of a person's character, are occasions for
the expression of a conservative object - that disowned internal self state
that has been preserved intact during childhood. When a person goes 'into' a
mood, he becomes that child self who was refused expression in relation to his
parents for one reason or another. Consequently moods are often the
existential registers of the moment of a breakdown between a child and his
parents, and they partly
indicate the parent's own developmental arrest [.....]. What had been a self experience in the
child, one that could have been integrated into the child's continuing self
development, was rejected by the parents, who failed to perform adequately as
ordinary 'transformational objects', so that a self state was destined to be
frozen by the child into what I have called a conservative object - subsequently
represented only through moods" (Bollas, 1987, pp115-116; bold emphasis
added).
To explain how he sees the whole thing working, he
introduces the term "mood space" (p99), a cognitive structure he
profiles as keeping its owner less than totally available for self-other
interaction, often, indeed, with the tacit acceptance of the mood in question
by the other(s) in question. [See now mood stabilisers.]
Mood
Disorders: This is the DSM-IV category cluster for disorders
where mood dysfunction is the primary diagnostic indicator. It consists of two
header categories, namely depressive
disorders (three disorders) and bipolar
disorders (six disorders).
Mood Reactivity: [See firstly differential
diagnosis, psychiatric.] Mood reactivity is a clinical sign used in the
differential diagnosis of-and-within the various depressive disorders,
especially atypical depression. It refers to the ability of some types
of dysphoria to flip temporarily to euphoria in response to
an enjoyable life event experience, or vice versa in response to a painful one.
Mood Space: See Bollas's (1987)
contribution to the entry for mood.
Morphe: [Greek = "form, shape".] See substance.
Mother
Archetype: See archetype.
Motivation
Questionnaire (MQ): See personality, motivation and.
Motor
Hierarchy: The ability to initiate
voluntary physical behaviour is known as "praxis", and (because anything voluntary
involves what we like to refer to as "the will") praxis has been a
traditionally difficult area for the cognitive theorist. For one thing, there
is the philosophical problem that nobody knows what the will actually is, and
for another, there is also the technical problem of explaining how ideas (i.e.
thoughts, images, or intentions) might be retrieved from some initially
timeless representational state - a structural memory trace of some sort - and
converted into a time-sequenced succession of behaviours. This latter is the
problem of motor sequence, and it has been around for some time, having been stated
very forcefully by Lashley (1951) in a paper entitled "The Problem of
Serial Order in Behaviour". The standard explanation is that the motor
memory for a particular piece of behaviour is capable (a) of being reactivated
as a single unit whenever its performance is required, and (b) of having its
component movements reactivated one by one. This sort of motor memory is
conventionally referred to as a "motor
schema", and the point about motor schemas is that by
definition they are organised hierarchically. There are at least two layers of
control in this hierarchy, because it must always start with the act of
volition, and always end with the muscles. Additional layers of organisation
can then be inserted between the top and the bottom, according to the demands
of the explanation at hand, with Weiss (1941) going for no less than six
"levels" in his model. [For more on the motor hierarchies involved in
speech production, see Section 4 of our e-paper on "Speech
Errors".]
Motor Schema: A motor schema is a long term memory structure capable of being accessed as a whole,
and then executed in parts. It is the "representation of a to-be-performed
movement" (Gallistel, 1980, p368). This implies that the memory trace has
a start and a finish, so to speak, unlike the memory traces for visual form,
say, where reactivation is all or nothing at any given point in time. The term
originated with Head (1926), was refined by Bartlett (1932), and was made
popular within motor theory by Schmidt (1975). Drawing on earlier work by Pew
(1966, 1974), Schmidt saw schemas as bringing together four different types of
information into a single motor memory, namely (a) the current state of one's
body in space, (b) what is to be achieved by a given movement, (c) what
feedback is to be expected during its execution, and (d) how successfully it
meets its aim.
MPD: See multiple personality disorder.
MPH: See methylphenidate.
MQ:
See
personality, motivation and.
MSBP:
See Munchausen
syndrome by proxy.
MT:
See machine translation or
mindfulness training according to context.
Müller,
Georg Elias: [German psychologist
(1850-1934).] [Click for
external biography] See the entry for consolidation
in the companion Memory
Glossary.
Müller,
Friedrich Max: [German linguistic
philosopher (1823-1900).] [Click for external
biography]
Müller,
Johannes Peter: [German physiologist
(1801-1858).] [Click
for external biography] See psychophysics.
Multiple Errands
Tests: [See firstly executive function and dysexecutive syndrome.]
The Multiple Errands Test is a simple test of the integrity of the
planning-execution components of human executive function, and, as such, is
commonly included as a frontal battery test. The test was developed by
Shallice and Burgess (1991), and involves taking the patient to a convenient
shopping mall, having previously briefed him/her with eight tasks. Six of the
tasks are shopping list tasks such as "buy a brown loaf", and the
seventh is to be back at a nominated rendezvous point after 15 minutes. The
eighth task is to obtain and write down four complex facts [such as the name of
the shop most likely to sell the most expensive item, or a particular bank
exchange rate]., and requires the subject to [Compare Six
Elements Test.]
Multiple
Personality Disorder (MPD): [See
firstly personality.] This is the
notion of an abnormally constructed mind, in which the conceptualisation of
personal identity has failed to reduce to a single serviceable persona. It is a mind in which the horizontal
layering - that which places the unconscious,
the preconscious, and consciousness in ascending order, for example - is divided again vertically into two (or more) relatively
self-contained independent domains [for more on this, see Stern (2002) in the
entry for dissociative identity disorder]. The name given to this
vertical compartmentalisation is "dissociation", and one
common outcome is a "multi-yolker" of a soul, so to speak, a single mind
capable of flicking from persona to persona whenever some secret trigger is
pulled or some old discomfort looms anew. The notion of multiple personality
first appeared in folklore and literature, in works such as Robert Louis
Stevenson's "Dr. Jeckyl and Mr. Hyde" (1886). The formal scientific
literature opened with a case reported by Paracelsus in 1646, Gmelin added another in 1791, and Rush (possibly the only psychiatrist
ever to sign a Declaration of Independence?) another in 1812. Mitchell (1816)
reported the case of Mary Reynolds, who would switch from a
melancholy and shy personality to one which was "buoyant" and
"fond of company" every few weeks from her late teens to her
mid-thirties, whereupon she stayed in her sociable self until her death at age
61 years. Then there were Despine's (1840) Estelle (then aged 15
years), who was paralysed in one self but mobile in another, and Azam's (1887) Félida
X, whose two personalities were so equally balanced that they both
considered themselves the rightful host! The early two-personae reports were
followed by higher-order multiples. For example, one of Janet's early career
cases while he was at Le Havre was Léonie (at least three personae) .....
ASIDE: Ellenberger (1994) explains that when Janet presented
Léonie at a case conference in 1885,
the session chair, Charcot, was so
impressed that he arranged for Janet to join him at the Salpêtrière in Paris,
where he was conducting his ground-breaking investigations into hysteria.
Prince (1906) reported on case Christine Beauchamp (four
personae) [in fact, it was Prince who helped establish the term
"dissociation" in the literature, using it in the title of his
paper]. Prince (1917) reported on one Dora Fisher (three
personae, capable of changing up to 50 times a day as the
alters got exhausted), and Thigpen and Cleckley (1957) reported on Eve
(initially two personae, with a third emerging during treatment). More recent
high-profile cases include Schreiber's (1973) case Sybil Dorsett (a
16-yolker!), Schoenewolf's (1991) case Jennifer (seven personae),
and Cameron
West (24!!).
ASIDE: Cameron West is something of an MPD celebrity, in
fact - check out his website
As to the aetiology of MPD, Putnam (1989) believes he knows
at least one of the underlying causes, thus [a long passage, heavily abridged] .....
"The linkage between childhood trauma and MPD has
slowly emerged in the clinical literature over the last 100 years, although
this association is obvious to any clinician who has worked with several cases.
[.....] Starting in the early 1900s, a few reports implicated traumatic life
experiences, such as a parental death, in the development of MPD [citations].
Goddard (1926) was the first to mention sexual abuse in connection with his
case; however, he strongly implied that he did not believe his patient's report
of incest, which he considered a 'hallucinosis
incestus patris' [.....]. Morselli's (1930) patient, Elena F, recovered memories of her father's incestuous assaults
during the course of violent abreactions in therapy. These memories were later
confirmed by independent sources [citation]. Taylor and Martin (1944), in their
review of MPD [.....], noted the role of 'severe conflicts' in the origin of
MPD, but did not elaborate. [.....] The National Institute of Mental Health
(NIMH) survey of 100 MPD cases found that 97% of all MPD patients reported
experiencing significant trauma in childhood [citation]. Incest was the most commonly reported trauma (68%), but other forms
of sexual abuse, physical abuse, and a variety of forms of emotional abuse were
reported. [.....] Sexual abuse is the most frequently reported type of
childhood trauma in MPD patients [and t]he most
commonly reported form of sexual abuse is incest [citations]. In most instances, this is father-daughter
incest or stepfather-stepdaughter incest [.....]" (Putnam,
1989, pp46-48).
Hedges adds .....
"The vast
majority of reported cases are women [80-90%]. The chief aetiological
hypothesis is exposure to overwhelming experiences in early childhood, usually
of a violent, intrusive sexual nature. The supposed early traumas are often
reported as some form of incest perpetrated by an older male, though mothers or
other women are frequently named as co- or passive collaborators. [.....] In
the earlier literature persons with multiple personalities are generally spoken
of as being exceptionally intelligent with IQs often estimated to exceed 130
[.....] High intelligence has sometimes been postulated as a key factor
which kept the person from becoming seriously psychotic" (1994/2006 online)
Putnam then offers a "developmental model"
of multiple personality. His basic proposal is that "the potential for
multiple personalities" (p51) is in all of us, and that it is one of the
tasks of normal development to "consolidate" what is there into
"an integrated sense of self" (ibid.).
Depression is the single most common presenting symptom, with sudden mood
swings. The typical "host" personality is characterised by low
self-esteem, is overwhelmed, and anhedonic, possibly accompanied by difficulty
in concentrating, fatigue, sexual difficulties, and crying spells (ibid.).
Rejection is an especial problem, thus .....
"Multiples are
exquisitely sensitive to any form of rejection and will often perceive it where
none is intended. Responses [.....] may include self-mutilation, suicide
attempts, fugue episodes, and missed sessions. [Indeed,] many multiples will
repeatedly force the therapist into acceptance-rejection situations as part of
the testing that goes on in therapy. The basis for this sensitivity lies in an
MPD patient's past history. To be an abused child is to be profoundly rejected
by the people who are supposed to love and care for the child. Many multiples
report creating personalities whose function was to be pleasing to their
abusers in an effort to reduce the rejection and abandonment to which they were
subjected. [.....] Rejection by an important person may also have been a
prelude to an abusive episode. In some cases, one parent's rejection would
signal the other parent that that parent could now do what he or she wished.
This sensitivity to rejection is often compounded by later experiences in adult
life. Many multiples have experienced important relationships ending painfully
and unexpectedly because of something that they 'did' but were not aware of.
A common scenario is for one alter to sabotage the
relationships of the host or another alter" (Putnam, 1989, pp172-173;
emphases added).
Then there is all the secrecy .....
"The theme of secrecy
permeates all therapeutic work with MPD patients. Secrets exist on many levels.
Alters keep secrets from the host, from the therapist, and from one another.
The secrets involve past experiences and present behaviour. Much of the
treatment involves the slow unwrapping of secrets and the processing of their
contents. [.....] There are several dynamics between patient and therapist that
may be involved in further preventing the patient from revealing secrets [.....
However,] the secrets of the past are not the only secrets kept by multiples.
In the vast majority of cases, they have continued to live a life of secrets.
They have kept their true nature, multiplicity, hidden from others and often
from themselves. They have learned to compensate and cover for time loss and
its associated inconsistencies in their behaviour. Many multiples lead
double and triple lives" (pp173-174; emphasis added).
These secrets can only be
worked through once a serviceable relationship has built up between the
therapist and the patient. Unfortunately, Putnam warns that every interaction
with a multiple is "at some level a test" (p175), usually, directly
or indirectly, of their trustworthiness. He also warns (a) that regression is
an "almost inevitable" concomitant of any abreaction that may
eventually be obtained, and (b) that therapists need to be on the look-out for
"recapitulation of the abuse", that is to say, reliving of the
events, thus .....
"For example, most
sexually abused multiples will have promiscuous alter personalities who set the
patients up for traumatic sexual experiences. A common scenario involves a
promiscuous personality's picking up an abusive sexual partner and then turning
the body over to the frightened and often frigid host at the height of sexual
degradation. [.....] The dynamics of re-enactment are complex, but probably
include several driving forces. The traditional view is that re-enactment is an
attempt at achieving a belated mastery of the trauma [.....]. I believe,
however, that a second dynamic is more important in MPD patients: this is the
attempt to transfer remembered pain across the amnesic boundaries of the alter
personalities. Part of the therapeutic effect of abreaction is the wider
sharing of past traumatic experiences" (p179; emphasis added).
In Putnam's experience,
therapists also need to beware MPD transference reactions, because these are likely to be
"highly complex" (p184), thus .....
"The alter
personalities of a multiple [] may have semi-independent transference reactions
to the therapist [..... ultimately] because many of
the alters will have different, semiautonomous reactions to the same stimulus.
For example, if a therapist physically touches a multiple, some alters may have
a transference experience of the therapist as an important childhood figure
who was nurturing and comforting. Simultaneously, other alters may experience
the therapist as an abuser or rapist and the touch as extremely aversive. These
conflicting transference reactions may be expressed simultaneously,
sequentially, or in some combination thereof" (p184; emphasis added).
There is a similar need for
a clear head when it comes to countertransference - emotional reactions on the part of the therapist.
Thus .....
"Many of the alters of a multiple patient are likely to engender
distinct and separate countertransference responses within the therapist. Thus
a therapist working with a multiple may simultaneously be aware of hostility
toward one alter, sexual feelings toward another, and
a wish to hold and nurture a third alter. A therapist may feel pulled one way
and then another throughout a session with a multiple, struggling to identify
what is going on in the patient as well as within himself or herself. The disorder itself also evokes a variety of responses within a
therapist, ranging from fascination to fear" (pp 187-188).
Putnam advises therapists to
keep in mind who the patient is, because this can effectively change as the alters roll in and out! Therapy which began on the
"host" alter may, at the drop of a hat, need
to become therapy of one of its less stable (and differently constructed)
fellows! Putnam then explains how abreaction can be induced by either
hypnotherapeutic or pharmacological methods, but that, either way,
"regression and revivification" are "almost inevitable"
(p241) as a result. One of the reasons for this, he suspects, is that since
trauma usually occurred during early to middle childhood any alters which
formed in order to "absorb" (p241) the trauma will be
"frozen" at that age. Activating such alters will automatically
present as regression! It is also vital to deal with the abreacted material
once it has been awakened. The process here is known as
"reintegration" (p246), and calls for careful "integrative
psychotherapy" (ibid.), as follows .....
"If traumatic material,
relived through abreaction, is not brought into waking conscious awareness
within a short time [see note below - Ed.] after the abreactive experience,
much of it will be redissociated, re-repressed, or otherwise blocked from
conscious recall. The therapist can aid the patient in recalling this highly
charged material in a number of ways. The first and perhaps most important
intervention is to help the patient organise the
material into some sort of coherent form. The attempt to provide a time line []
is one example of a therapeutic structural intervention that can help the
patient organise the material for future waking recall. This will work with
some patients but not all. Different organising structures [.....] may be more
useful in some cases. [.....] 'Permission to feel' is also a therapeutic
intervention that aids in the integration of affects and somatic sensations. In
many instances, painful injuries were inflicted [but] the physical pain from
these experiences was dissociated and not fully felt at the time. [.....] The
therapist should make every effort to help the patient recover, re-experience, and
reintegrate split-off affects and somatic sensations, as these are probably the
most potent sources of everyday discomfort and dissociative behaviour"
(pp247-248).
ASIDE:
Putnam's
point about the short window of opportunity is entirely consistent with our own
semantic network database approach to mental organisation, wherein we
suspect that the long-term consolidation of memory takes place under the
control of some sort of biological "database currency" information whose
lifespan is measured in hours rather than days.
Finally, Putnam stresses
that the general therapeutic thrust should be towards integrating emotional
content which had previously been dissociated, even to accepting different
alters' accounts as independently true and valid by creating "a larger
understanding" (p248). This might be appropriate, for example, if one the alters related the story of the abusive intercourse as
"a brutal rape", whilst another described it as "an expression
of paternal affection" (p248). For her part, Franklin (1988) warns that
MPD is not always totally apparent. Many patients present "covertly",
with suppressed or hidden symptoms. She describes one such patient, Margaret, as follows
.....
"Eventually, I could distinguish four
personalities which were similar in external appearance and only slightly
different in voice and facial expression, but were more substantial than her
other dissociative states, in that they had a more distinct psychic structure
in terms of attitudes, affects, and functions and were more stably present.
They were: (1) Her presenting personality, who was depleted, depressed,
anxious, confused, subdued and had a soft, low-pitched voice; (2) a hostile
personality, who was angry because her parents did not love or care for her
properly; (3) a self-assertive, autonomous personality, who allowed her to get
her work done; (4) an efficient personality, who had a slightly higher-pitched,
brisk and clipped voice and who made definite plans for the future. These personalities
sometimes influenced and blended into one another before emerging. She also had
a number of personality states that emerged recurrently, but briefly. These
states had certain functions or represented identifications or sides of
conflicts or embodied certain defenses. A few showed distinct differences in
body appearance and facial expression and switched clearly, such as the child
states and the mannequin state. The states were (1) a superficial, conventional
state, (2) a numb state, (3) a paranoid state, (4) an identification with the
abuser state, (5) a hated, rejected state, (6) a superior, snobbish state, (7)
a hopeful, positive young adult state, (8) a robot or mannequin state, (9) a
defiant, rebellious state, and (10) several child states; a child with positive
feelings, a fearful, unloved abandoned child, and a dependent child. M.'s
behaviors and affects fluctuated as she changed states. Her states did not seem
to be connected to each other, and when she was in one state, she sometimes seemed
unaware of the others, but at other times she was co-conscious for more than
one state. She was often not aware of her conflicts when each side was
expressed by a different alter. Her personality states led her to show many
subdued and subtle signs of dissociation throughout her therapy."
The modern DSM-IV
classification for MPD is dissociative
identity disorder (but see also and compare Allison manifesto) so we continue the core narrative under that heading .....
[BREAKING RESEARCH: For more on the potential
role of "abnormal connectivity" in preventing or degrading the
maximal integration of multi-modular cognitive processing, see functional
connectivity
and its onward links.]
WAS THIS A SENSITIVE TOPIC FOR YOU?:
If for any reason you have been emotionally affected by any of the issues dealt
with in this entry, you will find suitable helpline details in the entry for personality
disorders or child abuse
as appropriate.
Multiple
Personality Disorder and Dissociative Identity Disorder Contrasted: [See firstly the separate entries.] Allison (1996/2006 online)
believes he has identified a number of fundamental differences between multiple
personality disorder (MPD) and dissociative identity disorder (DID). In what he
calls "the Allison Manifesto", he begins by contrasting the two
conditions as follows .....
"[MPD] is a real but rare dissociative disorder.
Alter-Personalities control the body until integration. The Original Personality
cannot have an "identity disorder" since she is never in charge.
[DID] is common but different in clinical manifestation from MPD. The Original
Personality is in charge of the body except when Alter-Personalities take over.
Hence, the Original Personality does have an 'identity disorder.' [Both
conditions] will manifest Imaginary Playmates that are misidentified as
Alter-Personalities. Also, people without dissociative tendencies can manifest
Imaginary Playmates. Such persons do not have a dissociative
disorder" (Allison, 1996/2006 online).
What Allison is giving us here is a major systematisation of two complex and overlapping clinical areas with far-reaching repercussions for phenomenology. Specifically, he is taking two of the three classical divisions of the soul and giving us a clinician's eye view of how they are built, how they ought to be integrated, and how - in the disorders named - they sometimes fail to integrate. The two divisions are the "emotional self" and the "intellectual self". He calls the cognitive side "the Essence". Now the reason this all matters so much is that these two basic types of self are prone to "separate by a process called dissociation", and dissociation, as we have argued elsewhere, is the process of semantic network construction put into reverse. A disassociated self cannot truly be understood, we submit, unless the processes of putting it together in the first place are understood. Indeed, if we follow this argument to its logical conclusion, if the secret of semantic network construction is to have a comprehensive data model, then a dissociated mind is that same data model, but with corrupt or missing data model relationships. Allison's argument then continues .....
"Artificial Dissociation of the Essence from the Emotional Self can occur during hypnosis in highly hypnotizable experimental subjects. [.....] Dissociation occurred naturally in patients with MPD before the age of seven, when they perceived a life threatening situation. The Essence's primary duty is to preserve the life of the individual. Therefore it dissociates from the Emotional Self when such a situation occurs. This is the first dissociation to occur in a person who then develops MPD. Until age seven, the child's mind is not mature enough to cope with such a danger without needing to flee. Since physical flight is usually impossible, she flees inside her mind. To be able to have MPD, a person must be a Stanford Grade V+ hypnotizable person. In the family of a child with MPD, the parents are polarized. From the child's point of view, the roles of the parents are being reversed constantly. The child is the sole target of abuse by the caretakers, and the other children are treated fairly. Family secrets are implanted in the child with MPD. This keeps the abuse ongoing" (Allison, 1996/2006 online; emphasis added).
What happens next is shrouded in the mysteries of self and personality, and Allison assigns a key role to what he calls the "inner self helper" (ISH). The argument is so important that we reproduce it in two paragraphs, the first relating to MPD and the second to DID .....
"In MPD, the first dissociation is the Essence separating from the Emotional Self. The Essence then takes on the assignment of Inner Self Helper (ISH), and the Emotional Self is sent into hiding. The ISH makes all Alter-Personalities, the first being one of many False Front Alter-Personalities. Then others are made in this order: Persecutors, Helpers, Identifiers, and Disabled. The ISH makes all Alter-Personalities from the potential characteristics of the Original Personality. Therefore, there is a limit to the number of Alter-Personalities which can be made. When a client with MPD claims to have hundreds of Alter-Personalities, most are Imaginary Playmates, as the ISH has a limited supply of personality traits available. The ISH cannot create more than 70 Alter-Personalities per person. Therapy is done only with Persecutor Alter-Personalities to reform them into Helpers. All of the reformed Persecutor Alter-Personalities are then layered onto the Emotional Self. That process is called Psychological Integration. Then the ISH reverts back to being the Essence. [.....] After the Emotional Self has gone through the same experiences she did not handle while dissociated, the Essence will reintegrate into her, in a process called Spiritual Integration. This is the final healing step" (Allison, 1996/2006 online).
"Dissociation also occurs naturally in DID patients, when they have a need for protection from a perceived assault after the age of seven. The personality is mature enough to stay in executive control of the body. However, she has not learned to protect herself from assault. The Essence makes Alter-Personalities to protect the body. In a person with DID, the Essence has not dissociated. A small number of Alter-Personalities are created by dissociation to deal with specific stressful situations. Therapy consists of teaching the patient to handle these problems. This makes the Alter-Personalities obsolete. The Emotional Self makes the Imaginary Playmates out of human feelings. Their behavior is unpredictable. They change over time and are either inside or outside the physical body. Imaginary Playmates do not have amnestic barriers as do Alter-Personalities. Imaginary Playmates can be used to exact revenge. In contrast, Persecutor Alter-Personalities are angry at the actual abusers, and they will focus that anger at them or others who mimic their behavior. Since Imaginary Playmates are made by the Emotional Self, they must be destroyed by the Emotional Self. Imaginary Playmates can be made by anyone. To confuse imagination with dissociation causes understandable skepticism regarding the dissociative process" (ibid.).
Allison then provides us with a valuable basis for the comparison of MPD and DID, in which he distinguishes the two conditions on 15 separate criteria, as follows .....
#1 Age of Onset: MPD = before seventh birthday; DID = Age seven or older.
#2 Setting: MPD = parental home; DID = Parental home, community, school.
#3 Reason: MPD = " Physical survival after sexual, physical, and/or emotional assault by primary caretaker(s)"; DID = " Need to protect self from an abuser; Birth Personality unable to defend self" (emphasis added).
#4 First Dissociated Entity: MPD = " Essence, in savior role of Inner Self Helper (ISH)"; DID = " Defensive alter-personality ".
#5 Second Dissociated Entity: MPD = " False-front alter-personality designed by ISH to placate abuser(s)"; DID = " Often none. If any, another defensive alter-personality from another assault".
#6 Role of Original Personality: MPD = " Abdicates executive control of body until allowed out by ISH in therapy during adulthood "; DID = "Stays in executive control of body ".
#7 Personality Seeking Therapy: MPD = Latest false-front alter-personality; DID = "Birth Personality ".
#8 Types of Alter-Personalities: MPD = False-fronts, persecutors, rescuers, handicapped, identifiers; DID = Hostile protectors (from beatings); Sexually aggressive ones (from rapes).
#9 Number of Alter-Personalities: MPD = Many -- 10 to 60 frequently; DID = Few, frequently only one.
#10 Suicide Risk: MPD = High, frequently hospitalized for suicide prevention; DID = Low, unless incarcerated and feeling hopeless & helpless.
#11 Therapy Plan: MPD = [external reference given]; DID = Individualized, based on reason for creation of the alter-personality.
#12 Role of ISH in Said Therapy: MPD = Co-therapist; DID = None; No ISH exists, only the patient's non-dissociated Essence!
#13 Major Elements in Therapy: MPD = Hypnotic age regression with abreaction, reframing, acceptance, and discharge; DID = Coping skill training to make the alter-personality unnecessary in today's world (assertiveness training, occupational training, supportive psychotherapy).
#14 Integration Process: MPD = First Psychological Integration of all alter-personalities into the Original Personality, then Spiritual Integration of the Original Personality with the ISH; DID = As Birth Personality learns to do for himself what the alter-personality has done for him since childhood, alter-personality atrophies from disuse.
#15 Therapy While Incarcerated: MPD = not theoretically an option; DID = good.
Multiple Self-Organisation: See multiple personality.
Multi-Programming: [Computing Term.] As applications of
computer electronics became ever more sophisticated during the 1950s, one of
the main problems to emerge was that the speed and capacity of the resulting
computer hardware started to exceed that which could practically be used by
computer programs needing to read from or write to data files [given that this
is a much slower process than computation pure and simple]. It therefore made
sense to allow several programs "simultaneous" access to a given
machine, with each program vacating the CPU
during its slower input-output operations. This arrangement is known as "multiprogramming". In one
particular early machine's case, up to 16 programs could be managed
concurrently, and it was left to the job
execution logic to sort out their relative priority [for more of the detail
here, see Section 1.2 of the companion resource].
The
idea of several programs competing with each other for limited resources has
since become popular in modern theories of biological attention and high level
motor control, especially those of the Norman-Shallice
type. For specific examples, click here or here. [Compare multi-tasking.]
Multi-Tasking (1/2/3/4/E): [See firstly job execution scheduling and
multi-programming.] (1) The term "multi-tasking" first
emerged in the computing industry [see preceding entry], and then, by analogy,
soon percolated into other important areas of academic interest, such as (2) management science (where it referred to the allocation
of more than one task to a given worker), (3)
cognitive science (where it
refers to the ability of a control system to plan, authorise, and execute with
full protective monitoring, more than one series of motor programs simultaneously),
as well as (E) into everyday English (where it has become a
fancy-sounding phrase for doing more than one thing at a time). Multi-tasking
is also relevant within (4) cognitive
ergonomics, because when the mechanisms let you down for some reason it
invites a state of cognitive overload
and can result in mistakes being made - see multi-tasking, human error and, immediately below.
Multi-Tasking, Human Error and: [See firstly multi-tasking.]
When computer designers first invented virtual machine operating systems
in the early 1960s, the better to support multi-programming applications, they immediately
found that there was a strict practical limit to the number of different users
who could be accommodated on a given machine before performance as a whole
started to deteriorate. What was happening at this tipping point was that the
system overhead for "rolling in" [tantamount, as a process, to
"re-attending to" in biology] a particular user's subset of machine
resources was starting to take up an ever greater proportion of the total
available resources. The machine was - in trade parlance - "thrashing", that is to say, getting
nowhere; it was so busy taking note of what it had to do next and with what,
and it had so many people to do this with, that it had no time left actually to
do it. Similar considerations seem to operate in biological information
processing systems, where they set the upper limit for the number of
concurrently active mental tasks which can productively be handled while
multi-tasking.
ASIDE: The exact numerical limit
is in fact a function of the size and complexity of the tasks. It might be one
major task and a couple of small, non-urgent, tasks, or perhaps two or three
medium-sized ones, or perhaps four or five small ones. Computers use the job
execution scheduling component of their operating system to sort this out; little is yet
known about the equivalent biological mechanisms.
It follows that the forensic
study of human disasters needs to cover the possibility of thrashing, and,
happily, it already does - although it knows it by the more formal term "cognitive
overload". The pivotal paper here is Norman and Bobrow (1975), complete with its
distinction between "data-limited" and "resource-limited" mental processes [for
details of which, see the companion
resource on "Resource Allocation Theory"], and the canonical
theory is the Norman-Shallice model of Supervisory Attention. Against this theoretical
background, Rubinstein, Meyer, and Evans (2001) stay within the supervisor
metaphor by describing the brain's executive control processes as the mind's
"inner CEO" [= "Chief Executive Officer"]. They measured
the effects of task familiarity on subjects' ability to switch between
mathematics tasks of varied complexity, and found as follows
.....
"[F]or all types of
tasks, subjects lost time when they had to switch from one task to another, and
time costs increased with the complexity of the tasks, so it took significantly
longer to switch between more complex tasks. Time costs were also greater when
subjects switched to tasks that were relatively unfamiliar. They got 'up to
speed' faster when they switched to tasks they knew better" (APA Press
Release, 2001/2007
online).
ASIDE: Rubinstein et al's
"rule activation time" is a subcomponent of overall reaction
time (RT),
and RT studies are one of experimental psychology's
oldest and most highly respected research methodologies. Readers unfamiliar
with this particular research tradition should check out the companion resource
on "Motor Programming" before proceeding. Note especially Davis's
(1957) analysis of the subcomponents of RT, and Smith's (1959) modular layout
for a "linear
predictor", as a prerequisite of effective "predictive control". For an updating review of this area, see
Marois and Ivanoff (2005/2007
online).
David Strayer, Principal
Investigator at the Applied Cognition Laboratory, University of Utah [homepage] has been
studying the multi-tasking implications of mobile phone use while driving since
2001. His basic concern is as follows .....
"People regularly
engage in a wide variety of multitasking activities when they are behind the
wheel [..... possibly] trying to make the time spent
on the roadway more productive [citation]. Unfortunately, because of the
inherent limited capacity of human attention [citations], engaging in these
multitasking activities often comes at a cost of diverting attention away from
the primary task of driving" (Strayer, Drews, and Crouch, 2006, p381).
In one study, the Utah team
found that cellphone distraction produced as "profound" an impairment on driving skills as a blood alcohol
concentration of 80 mg/litre [the legal limit for UK drivers is 800 mg/litre -
Ed.] (Strayer, Drews, and Crouch, 2006). Here are some
specific averages .....
Measure |
Alcohol |
Baseline |
Cell Phone |
brake reaction time (ms) |
779 |
777 |
849 |
maximum braking
force |
69.8 |
56.7 |
55.5 |
speed (mph) |
52.8 |
55.5 |
53.8 |
mean following
distance (m) |
26.0 |
27.4 |
28.4 |
time to collision
(s) |
8.0 |
8.5 |
8.1 |
These and related data were consistent with the
general belief that cell phone use was as prejudicial to road safety as intoxication,
although the functional locus of the impairment was not necessarily the same,
as now summarised .....
"On the one hand, we found that intoxicated
drivers hit the brakes harder, had shorter following distances, and had more trials
with TTC values less than 4 s. On the other hand, cell phones drivers had
slower reactions, had longer following distances, took longer to recover speed
lost following a braking episode, and were involved in more accidents. In the
case of the cell phone driver, the impairments appeared to be attributable, in
large part, to the diversion of attention from the processing of information
necessary for the safe operation of a motor vehicle [.....]. These
attention-related deficits are relatively transient (i.e., occurring while the
driver is on the cell phone and dissipating relatively quickly after attention
is returned to driving)" (op. cit.,
p388).
Munchausen Syndrome: This is Asher's (1951) term
for one of the most conceptually mystifying of the factitious disorders,
and one of Feldman's (2004) four "disorders of simulation"
(xiii). Its clinical signs [and with Munchausen Syndrome you have to
distrust half the signs and all the symptoms] are illustrated by case, Sandra, who duped her doctors into a precautionary double mastectomy because
(she claimed) she wanted her husband
to divorce her.
ASIDE: We have highlighted the phrase "she
claimed" because the whole point about skilled manipulators is that they
are just that, skilled manipulators. They are blessed with highly developed theory of mind skills, and have a
highly developed sense of "what sounds right" in explaining things
away as insignificant. In short, they use words the way chameleons use colour
(and not always so benignly either).
Referring to case,
Libby and case, Rhonda, Feldman
(2004) contrasts Munchausen pathology with other forms of factitious disorder,
as follows .....
"In Munchausen syndrome, material needs, as well
as burning psychological problems, can motivate a patient's behaviour. [.....]
Libby was primarily a Munchausen patient, not a malingerer. She was motivated
principally by her emotional needs rather than tangible reward. [..... On the
other hand,] Rhonda's deceptions were multi-faceted and lasting, [indicating]
factitious disorder but not [its] most severe subtype, Munchausen syndrome.
Feigned illness was not all there was to her life; in addition, she stayed in
the same town and avoided any hospitalisations [.....]. Unfortunately, like
most factitious disorder and Munchausen patients, she refused to admit to the
deceptions; therefore, she could not be treated for her true ailment,
factitious disorder. Libby and Rhonda suffered from additional mental
disorders. The most important one - one that is seen in the majority of cases
of factitious disorder and Munchausen syndrome - is borderline personality disorder. [.....] As both of these patients
carried out their disease portrayals, they flitted around medical professionals
like moths around a flame, taking risks and manipulating others as borderline
patients typically do. Libby surrounded herself with counsellors and
therapists; Rhonda found a mentor who would become mother, sister, best friend,
and guardian angel" (Feldman, 2004, pp10-11; emphasis added).
[For additional scenarios, see Aleem and Ajarim (1995/2006 online). See then and compare Munchausen
syndrome by proxy.]
Munchausen Syndrome by Internet: [See firstly Munchausen
syndrome.] This is Feldman's (2004) term for Munchausen Syndrome delivered
in or over cyberspace, that is to say, using Internet "chat rooms" or
the like, mobile telephony, or any other modern electronic device.
Munchausen Syndrome by Proxy (MSBP/MBP): [See firstly Munchausen
syndrome.] [A.k.a. "Meadow's syndrome".]
This is Meadow's (1977, 1982) term for probably the most sinister disorder
of simulation, one in which a psychologically disturbed mother (or
equivalent long-term caregiver) either fakes clinical signs in a child in her
care [see case, Kay
(Meadow, 1977)] or else commits potentially lethal assault upon them [see case,
Kathy Bush] . MSBP thus constitutes the
legally critical point at which "factitious disorder becomes abuse"
(Feldman, 2004).
ASIDE: Readers who are not already fully familiar with what
is involved in MSBP should check out the introductory cases mentioned above before
proceeding. A comprehensive case database is maintained by the Asher Meadow
Centre [visit now] for those who
disbelieve the introductories.
Apolo (1999/2006 online)
lists the following clinical signs as being readily (and regularly) feigned or
covertly induced, frequently over many months .....
apnea [= stopping breathing]; cardiac arrhythmia;
glycosuria; haematuria [= blood traces in urine]; haemoptysis [= spitting
blood]; hypoglycaemia; infection; oral bleeding; poisoning (either by overdose
or forced feeding), induced seizures; vomiting
Concerned that a large number of MSBP cases were still
being overlooked, Apolo also reminded clinicians of the seven most indicative
circumstantial symptoms and signs, as follows .....
MSBP
Circumstance #1: That the pathology
is both unexplained and persistent.
MSBP
Circumstance #2: That the child is
healthy in other respects.
MSBP Circumstance
#3: That both symptoms and signs are
puzzling.
MSBP
Circumstance #4: That the pathology
does not occur when the child is separated from the carer(s). [Feldman
(2004) calls this the "positive separation test".]
MSBP
Circumstance #5: That the core
pathology has only ever been directly witnessed by the carer(s).
MSBP
Circumstance #6: That the carer(s)
routinely decline offers of respite time away from the child.
MSBP
Circumstance #7: That
carers seem strangely less deeply worried about the prognosis than the
clinicans.
The legal position in the UK is currently [December
2006] in a state of some disarray following case, Sir Roy Meadow and case, David
Southall. The situation in the US is as follows .....
"MBP is not a mental illness even though the
behaviours and motivations are similar to factitious disorder, which is a
mental illness. The critical difference is in who is harmed: oneself
(factitious disorder) or someone else (MBP). [.....] Being homicidal does not
qualify as an emotional ailment. However, being suicidal does. By aiming her
deceptions at her child, not herself, the MBP
perpetrator unmasks herself as a perpetrator, not a patient. Her actions
constitute abuse, not mental disease. [In the US,] MBP maltreatment falls
decisively under the criteria contained in the Federal Child Abuse Prevention
and Treatment Act of 1974. This Act defines child abuse and neglect as 'the
physical or mental injury, sexual abuse, negligent treatment, or maltreatment,
of a child under the age of 18 by a person who is responsible for the child's
welfare, under circumstances which indicate that the child's health or
welfare is harmed or threatened thereby'. [.....] The main types of abuse
are emotional, physical, and sexual; neglect is categorised as physical or
emotional" (Feldman, 2004, p122).
As to prevalence .....
"A conservative estimate is that there are 1200
new cases of MBP reported per year in the United States. Documented cases of MBP
have come from more than 20 countries throughout the world and have appeared in
at least 10 languages. The continued recognition of MBP proves that MBP is not
simply a theory or a behaviour confined to Western
societies, but a pattern of actions constituting a specific kind of
maltreatment of international dimensions. The last point warrants emphasis
because groups have arisen that deny the very existence of [MBP]. Their
membership consists of individuals who are understandably bitter about having
been falsely accused and have important points to make about situations in
which the risk of misdiagnosis is heightened. However, it appears also to
include actual perpetrators who grasp the brass ring these groups offer to
conceal their crimes. Perpetrators who align themselves with the groups insist
upon their innocence and present themselves as victims who are being punished
for having the courage to speak out against physician incompetence. The group
members often target key professionals who have attempted to build awareness
about MBP. In an effort to destroy reputations, they have collected and
publicised personal information about these professionals and have sent
threatening e-mails" (Feldman, 2004, p123).
As to the underlying motivation, the jury is still
out. Feldman insists that MSBP is a crime rather than an illness, but
recognises that it is "often accompanied by emotional or psychological
disorders" (p127). Similarly, Schreier and Libow (1993) describe MSBP
mothers as essentially unwanted or uncared for; as victims themselves, of
emotional neglect. Feldman summarises this very messy situation as follows .....
"MBP perpetrators are motivated by an intense
desire for emotional gratification. [They] may simply adore the attention MBP
produces for them. Having an ill child brings them a certain kind of misguided
status. Their child's illness is their claim to fame, and they bask in
accolades from medical caregivers or the community about their devoted
parenting. [.....] The child's illness may bring about a closer relationship
between the parents. Arguments cease and the parents unit when faced with the
common adversity of a sickly child. This closeness may suit the mother, who
sustains it by keeping the child ill. [.....] MBP maltreatment allows the perpetrators
to express rage not only towards their children but also toward those whom they
see as responsible for their dissatisfying lot in life. For instance, they may
blame their own parents, who will be predictably distraught that their
grandchildren have perplexing ailments and who can therefore be 'punished' by
ensuring that the child is never cured. [..... Others] find gratification in
manipulating high-status professionals, such as doctors, and prestigious
institutions" (Feldman, 2004, p133).
Munchausen, Baron Hieronymus Karl Friedrich von: [German aristocrat-soldier-adventurer (1720-1797).] [Click for external
biography] Von Munchausen is noteworthy in the context of the present glossary
for having earned his living in later life by writing a magazine column in
which he somewhat embellished his life adventures, thus rather unfairly
bringing upon himself a reputation today as a class-defining liar and braggard,
a reputation which did not escape Asher (1951) when he was searching for a name
for the crime-cum-clinical-disorder which we now know as Munchausen syndrome.
Murray, Henry A.: [American psychologist (1893-1988).] [Click for external biography]
Murray is noteworthy in the context of the present glossary for his work on personality,
motivation and and the Thematic Apperception Test.
Myers-Briggs Type Indicator (MBTI): The MBTI is a psychometric
package for the assessment of Jungian personality types. It was pioneered by
the psychometrician Katharine C. Briggs, in the early 1900s, before
being upgraded in the 1920s to incorporate Jung's (1921) schematisation of
psychological types. It was then further developed by Briggs' daughter Isabel
Briggs Myers, before being deployed as an assessment package in the 1940s. It
was formally published as a testing instrument in 1962. In her introduction to
the 1981 edition of the package, McCaulley (1981) explains how it requires only
four basic personality dimensions, as follows .....
Dimension E-I:
The extremes here are Extraversion (E) and Introversion (I), according to
whether a person is primarily interested in "the outer world of actions,
objects, and persons" or "the inner world of concepts and
ideas" (McCaulley, 1981, p298; emphasis added).
Dimension S-N:
The extremes here are Sensing (S) and Intuition (N), according to whether a
person "prefers" to perceive "the immediate real practical
facts of experience and life" or else "the possibilities,
relationships, and meanings of experiences" (Ibid.).
Dimension T-F:
The extremes here are Thinking (T) and Feeling (F), according to whether a
person makes decisions "objectively,
impersonally, considering causes of events and where decisions may lead"
or else "subjectively and
personally, weighing values of choices and how they matter to others" (Ibid.).
Dimension J-P:
The extremes here are Judgment (J) and Perception (P), according to whether a
person prefers to live "in a decisive, planned, and orderly way, aiming to
regulate and control events" or else in "a spontaneous
flexible way, aiming to understand life and adapt to it" (Ibid.).
Since these four dimensions are held to be effectively
"orthogonal" (i.e. they are free to vary independently of each
other), any one person's type may be identified by scoring it on the four
dimensional codes which most describe him or her. Moreover, since the four
dimensions are also dichotomous, this gives us 24, or 16, different
Jungian types. These are conventionally shown in the literature as four-letter
acronyms such as ESTJ, where each
letter takes one of the two possible values for the dimension in question.
There are many online tutorials on the 16 MBTI types [we recommend this one for
starters], to which further reference can be made, if interested.
Myers,
Isabel Briggs: [American
psychometrician (1897-1979).] [Click for external
biography] See Myers-Briggs Type
Indicator.
Naive
Realism: [See firstly Realism.] This is both a major
philosophical orientation and a jumping-off point for a wider philosophical
adventure. The orientation is that already presented in G.2, and is here
explained in other words, courtesy of Wikipedia .....
"Naïve
realism is the common sense theory of perception. Most people, until they start
thinking philosophically, are naïve realists. This theory is also known as
“direct realism” or “common sense realism”. Naïve realism holds that the view
of the world that we derive from our senses is to be taken at face value: there
are objects out there in the world, and those objects have the properties that
they appear to us to have. If I have an experience as of a
large apple tree, then that’s because there’s a large apple tree in front of
me. If the apples on the tree appear to me to be red, then that’s
because there are objects in front of me, apples, that have the property
redness; simple" (Wikipedia).
The philosophical adventure is then that the everyday
intuitive account of perception does not actually hold a lot of water, thus .....
"Plausible
though naïve realism may be, it has serious problems, among which is the problem of the variability of perception. The same
object may appear differently to different people, or
to the same person at different times. The apples may appear to be red in the daytime,
but at dusk they are a shade of grey. If naïve realism is to be taken
seriously, and colours are out there in the world, then apples regularly change
colour depending on how much light is around them. It is much more plausible,
though, to think that the apples are the same as they ever were, that all that
has changed is our experience of them" (Wikipedia).
One way or another, the bulk of this glossary is
concerned with going beyond the common sense understanding of perception, but
readers interested in going straight in at the deep end will find no better
place to start than with the entry for consciousness,
Kant's theory of.
Narcissism: In everyday English, to be "narcissistic"
is to have an overly inflated opinion of one's own worth. The word was taken
from the proper name Narcissus, a Greek mythological character renowned
for having fallen in love with his own reflection [full story]. It was
used in this sense, for example, in Rousseau's 1752 play Narcissus, or Self
Love, and was thus a natural choice of term for 19th century psychiatrists
looking for a descriptor for a class of personality disorder characterised by a
pathological lack of humility in interpersonal relationships and leading to
impossible demands being made on the behaviour and affections of others. [See
now narcissistic
personality disorder.]
Narcissistic Personality Disorder: [See firstly narcissism.] This is one of
the eleven DSM-IV disorder groups
under the category header of personality
disorders. Its essential feature is "a pervasive pattern of
grandiosity, need for admiration, and lack of empathy that begins in early
adulthood and is present in a variety of contexts" (DSM-IV-TR, 2000,
p714). Their "grandiose sense of self-importance" may manifest itself
in their inflating their accomplishments and being generally boastful, and in
assuming that others share in that approval. Their lack of empathy shows itself
in difficulty (a) recognising, and (b) responding to, the feelings of others.
In addition .....
"These individuals are often envious of others or
believe that others are envious of them (Criterion 8). [.....] They may harshly
devalue the contributions of others [..... and] often display snobbish,
disdainful, or patronising attitudes (Criterion 9)" (op. cit., p715).
To the extent that poor self-esteem is an underlying
factor in NPD, such individuals are also very sensitive to criticism or defeat,
and they may respond to such setbacks with "disdain, rage, or defiant
counterattack" (ibid.). For this
reason, Vaknin (2003/2007 online) rather neatly
nicknames NPD "malignant self love". The rage and counterattack
aspect of the condition also leads it to be a cause of abuse, deserving, even,
a category of its own. For more on this side of things, see narcissitic rage.
Narcissistic Rage: [See firstly narcissistic personality disorder.] This is Heinz Kohut's (e.g., 1972) term for a
common and highly distinctive emotional and behavioural correlate of
narcissistic personality disorder, namely uncontrollable and socially
disruptive temper tantrums, occasioned by a perceived slight and of variable
intensity from mild annoyance to the most extreme fury. Kohut explains this darker side of the narcissistic
individual by tracing their adult narcissism back to a serious pathology in
childhood ego development. The critical failure takes place in the individual's
"selfobjects"
[one word, note]. Chessick explains his thinking here .....
"The concept of selfobject was introduced by
Kohut to help distinguish between object relations and object love. The small
child has object relations but not object love. The child relates to others as
selfobjects, in which the object is experienced as part of the self and having
no life of its own. There are two kinds of selfobjects: those who respond to,
confirm, and mirror the child's sense of greatness and perfection, and those to
whom the child can look up and with whom the child can merge. Selfobjects of the second category provide an image of calmness and
omnipotence which can be borrowed to provide narcissistic equilibrium"
(Chessick, 1985, p118).
The key process is called "mirroring", and involves the developing child carefully and
continually monitoring its caregivers for signs of approval or otherwise (using
them, in this vitally important respect, as "mirrors"). If a child
fails to get enough mirroring - and this can only be the fault of its
caregivers - then the narcissism which is normal at age two to five
years fails to be replaced by a more humble post-Oedipal organisation, and is
instead "split off" from reality and repressed. Here is Chessick again .....
"Kohut flatly disagrees with the hypothesis that
there is an inherent human aggressive drive which is only thinly protected by
the veneer of civilisation and accounts for the outbreak of war. In his view
human aggression arises in its most dangerous form out of narcissistic rage,
which in turn is a disintegration or by-product as a
consequence of the profound disappointment in self-objects. The
narcissistically vulnerable individual responds to actual or anticipated
narcissistic injury with shamefaced withdrawal or with narcissistic rage
[.....] The whole problem of 'preventive attack' and the boundless wish for
revenge [.....] becomes understandable as a situation in which narcissistic
rage actually enslaves the ego. Even the smallest narcissistic
wounds can produce the most astonishing demonstrations of narcissistic rage in
individuals who are narcissistically vulnerable" (Chessick, 1985,
pp136-137).
Vaknin (commercial
website) reminds us that narcissistic rage can be either
"explosive", that is to say, immediate and obvious, or
"pernicious", in which "the narcissist sulks, gives the silent
treatment, and is plotting how to punish the aggressor", and goes so far
as to blame narcissistic rage for a surprisingly high proportion of domestic
abuse. Taking a wider view of the phenomenon, Wolf (2001/2007
online) goes so far as to implicate narcissistic rage in war, where it
interacts with a dimension he calls "group helplessness", thus .....
"Perhaps the hottest
spots of narcissistic rage these weeks are in the Middle East. Both peoples,
the Palestinians and the Israelis, feel relatively powerless and helpless
vis-a-vis the other side [.....]. Both sides seem to have adopted the view that
through increasing violence they can destroy the other's will and power to
fight [.....] Of course, as anyone can see, that does not work. On the contrary, the increasing violence only increases the
experience of helplessness with an increase in narcissistic rage on both
sides" (op. cit., e4).
WAS THIS A SENSITIVE TOPIC FOR YOU?: If for any reason you have been emotionally
affected by any of the issues dealt with in this entry, you will find suitable helpline
details in the entries for child
abuse and infanticide
and/or partner abuse and/or toxic caring. The
Narcissistic Abuse website might also be of specific interest
and value.
Narrated Self: See self, narrated.
National Heroes, Psychodynamic Theory and:
"And when she could hide him [= Moses] no longer
she took for him a basket made of bulrushes, and daubed it with bitumen and
pitch; and she put the child in it and placed it among the reeds at the river's
brink" (Exodus, 2:3).
"Tarchetius delivered them [= Romulus and Remus]
to one Teratius, with orders to destroy them. But instead of that, he exposed
them by a river side, where a she wolf came and gave them suck" (Plutarch).
As has been repeatedly noted elsewhere [see, for
example, the entries for aggression,
institutionalisation of and identity,
comparative approaches to], 19th
century cultural anthropologists were fully aware that there were interesting
commonalities of myth between geographically separate cultures. There was,
however, no deep psychological theory to explain why this should be so until
the opening years of the 20th century, when theorists such as Jung and Rank
started to develop psychodynamic interpretations of human belief systems. One
of the most fascinating analyses is that provided by Rank in a book entitled The Myth of the Birth of the Hero (Rank,
1909/1914). Rank's substantive point was that the biblical story of Moses'
concealment and discovery repeats itself - mutatis
mutandis - in a suspiciously large number of the world's belief systems
[listed in the first textual extract below]. As described at second hand in Moses and Monotheism (Freud, 1939/1964),
the key and common elements of all these stories seem to be as follows .....
- the child is of
aristocratic or royal parentage
- its conception is
"preceded by difficulties" (p10)
- its birth is presaged by a
prophecy (dreamed or oracular) to the effect that the child will somehow grow
to threaten its father [we may take the story of Oedipus the Tyrant as typical here]
- the child is therefore
ordered put to death .....
- ..... only to be rescued by
humble surrogate parents (human or animal) and brought up in a place of safety
- once the child has grown
up, he rediscovers his true parents and takes revenge on his father-
Moses was not even the first to get the bulrush treatment.
Consider .....
"The oldest of the historical figures to whom
this myth of birth is attached is Sargon of Agade, the founder of Babylon (c.
2800 BC[E]). For us in particular it will not be
without interest to quote the account of it, which is attributed to him
himself: 'Sargon, the mighty King, the King of Agade am I. My mother was a Vestal, my father I knew not, while my father's
brother dwelt in the mountains. In my city, Azupirani, which lies
on the bank of the Euphrates, my mother, the Vestal, conceived me. Secretly she bore me. She laid me in a
coffer made of reeds, closed my doorway with pitch, and let me
down into the river, which did not drown me. The river carried me to Akki, the drawer of water. Akki, the drawer of water, brought me up as
his own son [and so on, in like vein]. The names most familiar to us in the
series which begins with Sargon of Agade are Moses, Cyrus, and Romulus. But in
addition to these Rank [..... includes] Oedipus, Karna, Paris, Telephos, Perseus, Heracles, Gilgamesh,
Amphion and Zethos, and others" (Freud, 1939/1964, Moses and Monotheism (Part 1) [Standard Edition, Volume 23], p11;
bold emphasis added).
Freud's own take on this commonality of myth was that
the secret driving factor was human sexuality itself, and specifically the
tensions of love and hate which made up the Oedipus complex, thus .....
"A hero is someone who has had the courage to
rebel against his father and has in the end vicariously overcome him. Our myth
traces this struggle back as far as the individual's prehistory, for it
represents him as being born against his father's will and rescued despite his
father's evil intention. The exposure in a casket is an unmistakable symbolic
representation of birth: the casket is the womb and the water is the amniotic
fluid. The parent-child relationship is represented in countless dreams by
pulling out of the water or rescuing from the water. When a people's
imagination attaches the myth of birth which we are discussing to an
outstanding figure, it is intending in that way to recognise him as a hero
[.....]. In fact, however, the source of
the whole poetic fiction is what is known as a child's 'family romance', in
which the son reacts to a change in his emotional relation to his parents and
in particular to his father. A child's earliest years are dominated by an
enormous overvaluation of his father [.....]. Later, under the influence of
rivalry and of disappointment in real life, the child begins to detach himself
from his parents and to adopt a critical attitude towards his father. Thus the
two families in the myth - the aristocratic one and the humble one - are both
of them reflections of the child's own family" (op.cit., p12; bold emphasis
added).
And again .....
"Let us, therefore, take it for granted that a
great man influences his fellow-men in two ways: by his personality and by the
idea which he puts forward. That idea may stress some ancient wishful image of
the masses, or it may point out a new wishful aim to them, or it may cast its
spell over them in some other way. [.....] We know that in the mass of mankind
there is a powerful need for an authority who can be
admired, before whom one bows down, by whom one is ruled and perhaps even
ill-treated. We have learnt from the psychology of individual men what the
origin is of this need of the masses. It is a longing for the father
felt by everyone from his childhood onwards, for the same father whom the hero
of legend boasts he has become. And
now it may begin to dawn on us that all the characteristics with which we
equipped the great man are paternal characteristics,
and that the essence of great men for which we vainly searched lies in this
conformity. The decisiveness of thought, the strength of will, the energy of
action, are part of the picture of the father" (op. cit., p109; bold emphasis added).
Natorp, Paul Gerhard: [German neo-Kantian
philosopher (1854-1924).] [Click
for external biography] Natorp firstly studied, and then taught, philosophy
at the University of Marburg, Germany, specialising in
Plato's Theory of Ideas. He put that
knowledge to work in Platos Ideenlehre
("Plato's Theory of Ideas") (Natorp, 1903), and is credited by Husserl (1913, p208) with having been
responsible for the distinction between awareness [Bewusstheit] and
intuition [Anschauung].
ASIDE: It is possible that Husserl may not have been aware in
1913 of Freud's (1896) "Letters to Fliess", because this
correspondence was not commonly available until the Masson collation in 1985.
In one of these letters, Freud sketches a five-layer model of the stages of
perception, with Bewusstsein as the highest level [check this out].
One of the key points of Natorp's philosophy is that
thinking is always "thinking an object" (Kim, 2003 online), but that by
the time it takes place that object has become a non-sensible thing! The secret
to this is as follows .....
"..... a very crucial
distinction must be made between two levels of phenomenality and of
objectivity, which for the purposes of this article shall be called
'first-order' and 'second-order.' A first-order phenomenon is the
psychic, subjective appearance that Natorp tacitly
acknowledge has a basis in sensibility, and which he calls the 'Phänomen letzter Instanz' or the 'phenomenon of final authority' (Natorp 1887:
273, 274; 1913b: 192); this first-order phenomenon is a 'Vorstellung,'
or 'representation,' [.....] The
question now is: what makes the second-order phenomenon a bona fide
objectivity, in contrast to the first-order phenomenon? Whereas the first-order
phenomena constitute private, lived subjectivity, not open to prediction or
even adequate description, Natorp's answer is that the second-order object is
constructed in accordance with laws of thinking, which as laws are in their
very nature objective, i.e., universally valid for any thinker. Therefore
objects (Gegenstände) lawfully determined will in principle be rationally
transparent to any other thinker, i.e., 'objective' (objektiv, gegenständlich)"
(Kim, 2003 online, p6).
Natural Experiment: [See firstly experimental method.] This is the name given to a
naturally occurring event which can be scientifically studied as if it
had been deliberately arranged. Its value lies in the fact that many
scientifically important variables - the effects of an earthquake, say - are
simply beyond control, and so cannot be "manipulated" in the strict
sense that ("true") experimenters like to manipulate their independent
variables. So what they do instead, is take
measurements in advance of the happenstance event and then wait patiently for
it to happen so that they can regard it as manipulated. For a more detailed
introduction to this topic, see the longer entry in the companion Research
Methods Glossary.
Needle Map: See perception, Marr's theory of.
Negative Self-Schema: See
self-schema, negative.
Neisser, Ulric: [American cognitive psychologist (1928-).] [Home Page]
See the separate entries for self, conceptual, self, ecological, self,
extended, self, interpersonal, and self, private.
Neo-Kantianism:
[See firstly consciousness, Kant's
theory of and Marburg School.]
Neo-Kantianism was a major force within German philosophical thought between
the 1870s and the 1920s and, as the name betrays, draws heavily on Kantian
theory. The principal exponents of neo-Kantianism were Cohen, Natorp, and Cassirer.
Network Database: [See firstly database.] The network
database is one of the two main types of database to have emerged in the last
half century (the other being the flat-file database). Specifically, it is
a database built to the guidelines laid down by the US Department of Defence's Conference on Data Systems Languages
(CODASYL) in the early 1960s, and therefore based on an implementation of Set
Theory using a combination of direct
access and chain pointer sets.
Neural
Correlates of Consciousness (NCC):
[See firstly mind-brain debate.]
This is Crick's (1996) term for the neurophysiological mechanism(s) which
correlate most closely with the mechanism(s) of mind, if indeed there is/are any. As such, the primary objective of a Reductionist solution to the mind-brain
problem is to decipher the NCC. Noë and Thompson (2004) describe this as the
search for the "matching content" of mind and brain.
Neural Network: [See firstly Connectionism.]
A "neural network" is a non-biological simulation of a biological cell
assembly, either (a) simulated "in hardware" using purpose-built
electronic circuitry, or (b) simulated "in software". [For further
details, see our e-paper
on "Connectionism".] CAUTION: Do not get neural
networks confused with neuronal networks, which are made out of real
neurons. EXCEPTION: Damasio (2002, p50) uses the term
"neural network" as a synonym for cell assembly.
Neuroanatomy: See basic
nervous system macroanatomy for the structures visible to the naked eye,
and basic
neuron microanatomy for the cellular and sub-cellular stuff.
Neuroethology: [See firstly ethology.]
Although the electrical stimulation of brain tissue had been a recognised
research technique since the late 19th century [see, for example, the work of
Caton and Ferrier in the companion Neuropsychology
Timeline] there was a considerable delay before advances in microtechnology
permitted experimentation on individual neurons. This sort of research called for
microelectrodes rather than electrodes, not to mention microhandling systems
capable of working on living organisms rather than sliced-up dead ones. One
breakthrough came with the discovery of the giant axons in the nervous system
of the squid (Young, 1936, 1944). These can be up to 1mm across (about fifty
times larger than the largest fibres in man) and are perfectly visible to the
naked eye. They are thus easy to work with, and many of the modern concepts of
neurotransmission derive from early work with the squid. It was against this
background that zoologists began to study the brain structures responsible for
instinctive behaviours such as locomotion and bird song, etc. Some early
studies were carried out in the 1960s, and the new science -
"neuroethology" - had become a popular research area by the early
1980s. One of neuroethology's
core notions was that of the central
pattern generator (CPG), an inherited neural circuit capable of being
excited as a unit in response to a precisely specifiable stimulus
configuration, and of then discharging over a period of time in a behaviourally
distinctive way. CPGs were thus the neural substrate for the expression of
unlearned behaviour in the field; the machinery behind Lorenz and Tinbergen's fixed
action patterns (FAPs). In a typical early study, Wilson (1961) showed that
the CNS of the locust can generate central discharges to the motor neurons of
flight in the absence of incoming
stimulation. Similarly, Dorsett, Willows, and Hoyle (1969, cited in Hoyle,
1985) identified a chain of neural impulses corresponding to the FAP for the
escape swimming of the mollusc Tritonia,
and were even able to elicit the same neural response in a dissected brain.
Willows and Hoyle (1969) describe the neuronal circuit producing this escape
response as consisting of "at least 30 cells" in each pleural
ganglion. This, and similar early studies, demonstrated the ability of brains
to produce specific behaviours "because there is a specific neural circuit
for the production of that behaviour" (Hoyle, 1985, p59).
ASIDE: Note the technical
constraint beginning to emerge here. Nowadays it is easy to insert a
microelectrode into a single neuron, but it remains difficult to do this to many neurons simultaneously. If you have 30 neurons to
monitor, therefore, you have to examine the circuit "bit by bit",
building up your overall picture gradually.]
A good early
description of how CPGs might work is provided by Kater (1974), following research
into the feeding behaviour of the snail Helisoma
trivolvis. Kater identifies five "events" making up the full
feeding FAP, and sees the problem faced by the nervous system, therefore, as
being how (a) to generate and (b) to coordinate these lesser events. Kater
postulates a controlling neuronal network situated in the buccal ganglion of
the snail's nervous system, and suggests that this consists of three
inter-related subsystems as follows:
(a) Protractor
Neurons: These are neurons which move the mandibles and the "buccal
rasp" into a position ready to pick up food.
(b) Retractor
Neurons: These are neurons which move the food back into the buccal cavity prior
to swallowing.
(c) Cyberchron
Neurons: These are neurons which form "the core of the central program
underlying feeding" (p1024). They control the overall timing of the
behavioural cycle by alternating the firing of the retractor and protractor
neurons. (The name derives from the Greek words kybern - to steer, and chronos
- time.)
Allen Selverston is
another who has painstakingly analysed invertebrate nervous systems. Using a
technique whereby individual neurons can be killed by exposing them to a
microbeam of laser light, his team has mapped the neuronal network responsible
for the stomach contractions of the Californian spiny lobster (Selverston,
Miller, and Wadepuhl, 1983). This is a complex of 30 neurons arranged into two
distinct CPGs, one controlling a rapid pumping movement in the pyloric region,
and the other controlling the mastication of large food particles by the three
internal teeth of the gastric mill region. Each CPG is a network of excitatory
and inhibitory neurons so arranged as to output neural bursts of the correct
pulse length and frequency. In order to bring all these observations together
into a single theoretical framework, Hoyle has formulated what he calls the
"orchestration hypothesis". This distinguishes between "command
(C) neurons" and "modulator (M) neurons", both of which can issue
instructions to a CPG. Command neurons are described as "commanding"
the behaviour in question, while the modulator neurons (and there may be
several) "fine tune" how it actually appears, and are seen as being
sensitive to hormonal factors. Work is active in this area, but again the problem
of the complexity of neural circuitry remains to be overcome, and work remains
restricted to invertebrates and simple vertebrates (and ideally those with
large and well spaced out neurons). Nevertheless typical recent advances are in
pushing up the number of neurons which can be analysed (Strumwasser, 1987,
cites "about 1000" involved the egg-laying behaviour of Aplysia), and in tracking down the
biochemistry of the hormonal events involved (Strumwasser continues by stating
the formula of, and successfully synthesising, the egg-laying hormone which
modulates the said behaviour).
Neurolinguistic Programming (NLP): This is Bandler and
Grinder's (1975) integration of a number of ideas drawn from academic
neuroscience and linguistics with Gestalt and other psychotherapy techniques,
to create a commercially fielded programme for personal improvement. The
technique is sold as the ability "to awaken the Giant within", by
making better than average use of the standard mechanisms of communication and
behavioural control available to everyone. NLP is nowadays sold as a
market-tested integration of training experiences, reflective tutorials, and
assessments. Some commentators regard NLP as "pseudoscience", others
as "a shrewd commercial formula". [For the fuller debate, click here.]
Neuromarketing: This
is the name given to the application of neuroscientific concepts and data to
marketing problems in the world of industry and commerce. As such, it is an
important branch of applied cognitive psychology, and a testing ground for a
number of long-standing psychological theories, not least those of attitude
change and behaviour change. It also draws heavily on the older
theories of mental philosophy and the psychology of the self, and
the latest thinking in the field of identification. [For further
details, see Carmichael (2004/2007
online).]
Neuron, Non-Spiking: Type of neuron whose normal
mode of operation involves transmitting graded potentials only (rather
than action potentials) during decremental propagation.
Neuronal Group: See consciousness, Edelman and Tononi's theory of.
Neuronal Network: A network of
neurons. Same thing as cell assembly. NOT A
NEURAL NETWORK!!
Neuroplasm: A neuron's
cytoplasm.
Neuroses,
Oedipal Theory of: See Oedipal theory.
Neuroses,
Seduction Theory of: See Seduction theory.
Neurotic Defenses: [See firstly defense mechanisms.]
Neurotransmission: Reduced to basics,
there are actually three ways for chemicals to leave a given cell, namely (a)
by simple diffusion through the cell membrane, (b) by passing out
through pores in the cell membrane such as the sodium ion channel
(possibly - but not necessarily - helped on their way by metabolic pumping),
or (c) by exocytosis, the releasing of synaptic vesicles of
concentrated agent. The major mechanism as far as the synapse is concerned is
exocytosis, where the agent in question is the neurotransmitter
substance, and the point of exit is the pre-synaptic side of the synaptic
cleft. The vesicles themselves are originally formed by "budding
off" the Golgi apparatus as soon as sufficient new agent has been
synthesised. They then migrate cell-internally though the cytoplasm
to the synaptic button. Once there, they are sensitive to calcium ion
concentration changes. Specifically, as an action potential arrives at
the synaptic button it depolarises the cell membrane. This opens
voltage-gated calcium channels and allows calcium ions from the interstitial
fluid to flood into the cytoplasm, forming - as Levitan and Kaczmarek
(1991) colourfully describe them - miniature "volcanos of calcium"
(p159) on the inner surface of the cell membrane. This sudden arrival of
calcium ions somehow renders the vesicle membrane more compatible with the cell
membrane, and this causes both membranes suddenly to coalesce [as when a
champagne bubble ceases to exist upon reaching the surface], thus spilling the
vesicle's contents out into the synaptic cleft, where the molecules (not the
vesicles any more) now migrate cell-externally to the adjacent cell. As
for what happens within the post-synaptic neuron, the key concepts are those of
binding and receptor sites. Phrased simply, the neurotransmitter
molecules now bind with (that is to say, fit onto) suitably shaped
molecules in the surface of that membrane. These receiving molecules are known
as receptors. [Compare poros.]
Neurotransmitter: [See firstly neurotransmission.]
The contents of the synaptic vesicles released from the pre-synaptic
neuron into the synaptic cleft. These chemicals induce a post-synaptic
potential in the receiving neuron.
Niederland,
William G.: [German (American from
1940) psychoanalyst (1904-1993).] [Click for
external biography] Niederland is noteworthy in the context of the present
glossary for his work on survivor
syndrome.
NLP: See
neurolinguistic programming.
NMDA: See
N-methyl-D-aspartate.
N-Methyl-D-Aspartate
(NMDA): NMDA
is the most common of the glutamatergic neurotransmitters. Grosjean and
Tsai (2007) have recently attributed a serious cognitive deficit to a
dysregulation of the NMDA system - see the sidenote at the end of the entry for
borderline personality disorder.
Node of Ranvier: This is the received name for the microscopic spaces between adjacent Schwann
cell sheaths on a myelinated axon [picture], which, by
reinstating ion flow across the axonal membrane (prevented elsewhere on the
axon by its myelin sheath), are the only points on such an axon where an action
potential can occur. [See now saltatory conduction.]
Noema: [(pl. noemata) <νοημα(τα)>
Greek = "thought, purpose, design; understanding, mind" (O.C.G.D.).]
[See firstly intentionality.] This classical Greek word for phenomenally
focussed ideation was specifically applied to philosophy by Husserl
(1913), because he needed a word for a more immediate form of perceptual
understanding than full intentionality, and he chose noema for the reasons set out below .....
"[Intentional]
experience is the consciousness of something [.....] and
so we can ask what can be said on essential lines concerning this 'of
something'. Every intentional experience, thanks to its noetic phase, is noetic, it is its essential nature to harbour in itself a
'meaning' of some sort. [.....] Corresponding at all points to the manifold
data of the real (reellen) noetic content, there is a variety of data
displayable in really pure [] intuition, and in a correlative 'noematic
content', or briefly 'noema' [.....]. Perception, for instance, has its
noema, and at the base of this its perceptual meaning" (Husserl, Ideas, pp237-238; bold emphasis added).
Noematic Core:
Alternative translation of noematic
nucleus.
Noematic Field:
See consciousness, Husserl's theory of.
Noematic
Nucleus: See consciousness, Husserl's theory of.
Noematical: This word means "originating, or existing, in
thought, or in the mind alone; noetic" (O.E.D.).
Noemics /
Noesis / Noetic: See the pump-priming
definitions in G.2.
Noetic
Phenomenology: See phenomenology, noetic.
Non-Decremental
Propagation: Propagation whereby an action potential at one point on a cell
membrane induces a full action potential either (a) at an immediately
adjacent point in the neural membrane, or (b) some way off at the next node
of Ranvier. Because each action potential consumes metabolic energy, its
power does not decrement (= decrease) with distance. [Compare decremental
propagation.]
Non-Existent Objects: See
consciousness, Meinong's theory of.
Non-Verbal Communication: This is the generic name for the range of gestural, postural,
facial, and phonological communication channels which humans have inherited
from their evolutionary past and which can assist, and at times even totally
replace, spoken language as a medium of human expression and comprehension [for
a fuller discussion of the mechanisms and issues at work here, see Section 3 of
our e-resource
"Communication and the Naked Ape". See also prosody in the present glossary.]
Norman-Shallice
Model (of Supervisory Attentional Function): This is perhaps the most popular modern model of the biological control hierarchy. Structurally, it is
a three-layer/five-box control hierarchy (similar to Craik, 1945) sculpted
on top of a sixth box containing the schema selection process. This latter
process is characterised as relying as much on inhibitory mechanisms as upon
excitatory, so that the momentary salience of one motor program comes in large part from a carefully synchronised
lack of "contention" from all the others (Shallice, 1982, p200).
McCarthy and Warrington (1990) provide a useful summary of the model's key
points, as follows .....
"Norman and Shallice (1980) and Shallice (1982)
have adopted a computational information-processing approach to modelling
disorders of 'executive' functions. Norman and Shallice took as their starting
point the distinction between habitual and novel action routines [and]
suggested that the selection and integration of these two classes of action
were based on different principles. Norman and Shallice proposed that control over the sequencing and
integration of the components required for complex but well-established
patterns of behaviour is mediated by hierarchically organised 'schemas' or
motor representations [.....]. In
driving to work the highest level of the schema might be a comparatively
abstract representation of the route. Such high-level schemas can call up subordinate 'programs' or
subroutines; thus 'driving to work'
will have component schemas including at the lowest level instructions to
muscles to press pedals and turn the steering wheel. Norman and Shallice
suggested that under many conditions we can function on "auto pilot",
selecting and integrating cognitive or behavioural skills on the basis of
established schemata. Once a schema has been triggered it 'competes' for
dominance and control of action by a process of inhibiting other schemas which
would be likely to conflict with it [.....] (a process
which they termed contention scheduling). When one needs to suppress an
automatically attractive alternative source of stimulation, to plan novel
solutions to problems, or to change flexibly from one pattern of behaviour to
another, the selection of schemas on the basis of the strength of their initial
activation might be disastrous. Norman and Shallice argued that, under these
circumstances, the selection of schemas was modulated by the operation of a supervisory
attentional system [which] can provide a boost to a schema's level of
activation, thereby enabling it to 'get ahead' in the competition for dominance
despite starting from a handicapped position" (McCarthy and Warrington,
1990, pp362-363; bold emphasis added).
More recently, Shallice and Burgess (1996) have
discussed the possibility that the Supervisory System itself "can be
fractionated into different subprocesses" (p1405). The supervisory system
concept is central (a) to human problem solving, and (b) to the deterioration
of same following brain injury. [For further details, see Norman (1990) and
our e-papers on Resource
Allocation Theory and Mode
Error in System Control.]
Noumena: See noumenon.
Noumenon: [(Pl. noumena).]
A noumenon is "an object of purely intellectual intuition, devoid of all
phenomenal attributes" (O.E.D.). Alternatively, it is "a basic
reality underlying observable phenomena" (Wikipedia). The noumenon is Kant's notion of that which logically
precedes the phenomenon, and which
cannot therefore be consciously known. They are instead grasped [our word,
chosen here to imply a less conscious form of knowing than knowing] "transcendentally". Consider .....
"By Kant's view, we can By Kant's view, we can make
sense out of phenomena in these various ways, but can never directly know the
noumena, the "things-in-themselves," the actual objects and dynamics
of the natural world. In other words, by Kant's Critique, our minds may
attempt to correlate in useful ways, perhaps even closely accurate ways, with
the structure and order of the universe, but cannot know these
"things" directly. Rather, we must infer the extent to which thoughts
correspond with things by our further observations of the manifestations of
those things that can be seen, heard, touched, smelled, tasted, and/or measured
in some way by instrumentation, that is, of phenomena" (Wikipedia).
Nous / Nous: [Pronounce to rhyme with
"mouse".] See noemics, noema, etc.
Nous Praktikos: [See
firstly nous.] This is one of Aristotle's two basic types of knowledge
(the other being nous theoretikos). For the reasons set out in
the companion entry, which see, nous praktikos may loosely be regarded
as the classical equivalent of the modern procedural knowledge and motor
skill rolled together.
Nous Theoretikos: [See
firstly nous.] In Classical Greek this phrase means, approximately,
"an intellect which, like a god, looks out over the world and reflects
upon what it sees", but this definition really only means anything if
prior consideration has been given to the phrase bios theoretikos, Aristotle's
term for perfection in life. Aristotle pondered this particular issue in both Ethics
and De Anima, and saw the key to
perfection as one's ability to take a god's perspective on the universe and on
humankind's position within it. And because the Greek word for god was theos,
this godlike way of thinking was described by the adjective theoretikos,
precisely as we use the word "theoretical"
in English today for the presumptuously godlike act of trying to understand how
things work. It is for this reason
that the Greek bios theoretikos has traditionally been translated as
"life of contemplation". In other words, the nous theoretikos
describes the sort of mental information processing seen in a person practising
a bios theoretikos. Here are two
indicative extracts from the Ethics, the first from Aristotle himself,
and the second from one of his editors .....
"But if a living being is deprived of action, and
still further of production, what is left but contemplation? It follows, then,
that the activity of God, which is supremely happy, must be a form of
contemplation; and therefore among human activities that which is most akin to
God's will be the happiest" (Aristotle, Ethics [1976
Thompson-Tredennick Translation; Barnes Edition]; Book 10, §1178b, p333).
"The Aristotelian contemplator is a man who
already acquired knowledge; and what he is contemplating is precisely this
knowledge already present in his mind. Contemplation is something like a review
or survey of existing knowledge: the contemplator is engaged in the orderly
inspection of truth which he already possesses; his task consists in bringing
them forward from the recesses of his mind, and arranging them fittingly in the
full light of his consciousness. [..... So the] Aristotelian contemplator
with a penchant for geometry will first read Euclid (or prove for himself the
theorems which Euclid contains) and then gaze inwardly on the orderly array of theorems and
deductions in his mind [..... and] by
contemplation he brings his knowledge once again to the forefront of his
mind" (Barnes, 1976, pp38-39; bold emphasis added).
So why does nous theoretikos matter? Well to
start with, because it contrasts with nous praktikos,
an intellect which is deed-related rather than thought-related and which therefore
merely serves its owner's day-to-day non-intellectual needs. Then
again because it complements the set of nous-related intellectual skills
proposed by Peters (1967) in his lexicon of Greek philosophical terms [not
least episteme, aisthesis, doxa, dianoia,
nous
pathetikos, and nous poietikos]. And finally
(and most importantly, given the context of the present glossary), because nous
theoretikos remains an active notion within modern cognitive science where
it conveys the same basic notion as the modern propositional knowledge (nous praktikos being a combination of procedural
knowledge and motor skill).
Nuclear Membrane: This is the outer
surface of the cell nucleus, that is to say, the layer which confines the nucleoplasm.
Outside the nuclear membrane there is cytoplasm. It is a two-layered
molecular structure, namely a bimolecular lipid layer (lacking the outer
"sandwich" of protein layers which characterises the cell membrane).
Nuclear
Self: See self,
nuclear.
Nuclear
System: See Freud's Project.
Nucleolus: (Pl: Nucleoli.)
This is a small spherical shaped structure, of which one or more may be present
within the nucleus. It consists mainly of RNA, and is where ribosomes
are first created (that is to say, prior to their migrating out into the cytoplasm
and making their way to the walls of the endoplasmic reticulum).
Nucleoplasm: This is the fluid
medium of the cell nucleus. It contains the nucleoli and the chromosomes.
[Compare cytoplasm and interstitial fluid.]
Nucleus: This is physically
and functionally the central component of the cell. It is a near-spherical
structure, containing the nucleoplasm, the nucleoli, and the chromosomes,
and is bounded by the nuclear membrane. Most cells have a single
nucleus, although muscle cells have several and red blood cells have none.
Null Set: In the context of set-structured network databases, a "null" set is a set which presently
has no members, and whose chain pointer
therefore points back to itself.
Nutritative
Soul: See soul, nutritative.
Nymphomania:
See hypersexuality.
OAT: See Object
Alternation Test.
OAT-PE: See Object
Alternation Test.
o-Awareness: See
object-awareness.
Object
(E/1/2/3): In everyday English, the
noun "object" is confusingly adept at switching its meaning at the
drop of a hat between object-as-physical-external-thing [e.g., "I believe
that the sun exists and is not a figment of my imagination"], object-as-current-focus-of-mentation,
real or imaginary [e.g., "I have in mind the sun / the Minotaur"],
and object as behavioural-end-purpose [e.g., "My object in all this is to
....."]. Those hearing or seeing the word manage remarkably successfully
to stay on top of this confusion by adjusting their interpretation
automatically to the context in which the word had been used. In mental
philosophy, however, this supportive context can often be obscure, and so the
precise meaning of the word is easier to miss. Worse, the everyday complexities
noted above are further distorted by conflicting theoretical usages of the
term, not least the following .....
(1) Object, Perceptual: As used in
the mental philosophy of aesthesis, the word "object"
connotes a thing in its everyday sense, that is to say, it is substance possessed of a form. In this sense, Kant, for example, happily used Objekt
and Gegenstand
within the same sentence for the English "object" (e.g., Critique, p147),
whilst for Husserl an object was the "determinable X in the noematic
sense" (p337). [Compare object
concept.]
(2)
Object, Psychodynamic: As used in
psychodynamic theory, an "object" is "that to which a subject
relates" (Daniels, 2007 online),
be it animate or inanimate, concrete or abstract. It is a percept [i.e.,
an object (1)] whose relevance
to the person in question is such that it warrants tracking through time.
Indeed, it is this quality of having something known about it which makes such
objects presences on the mental stage in the Baars-ian sense [see consciousness,
Baars' theory of]. Objects of this
sort are the content matter of the branch of psychodynamic theory known as "Object Relations Theory", which now see. [Compare object, transformational.]
(3)
Object, Data Encapsulating: As used in
computer science, an
"object" is the core concept in what has come to be known as the
"object-oriented" approach to computer programming [see now object-oriented computing]. Khoshafian
and Abnous (1990) introduce the history as follows .....
"..... in the late
1950s, one problem found when developing large FORTRAN programs was that
variable names would conflict in different parts of a program. [.....] The
designers of the language ALGOL decided to provide barriers to separate
variable names within program segments. This gave birth to the Begin ..... End blocks in ALGOL 60 [Citation]. Since the
variable names appearing within a block are known only to that block, their use
will not conflict with the use of the same variable name in other blocks of the
program. This was a first attempt at providing protection or encapsulation
within a programming language. Block structures are now widely used in a
variety of languages. [//] In the early 1960s, the designers of the language
SIMULA-67 [Citation] took the block concept one step further, and introduced
the concept of an object [thus laying] the foundation of object-oriented
languages and some of the object-oriented terminology"(Khoshafian and Abnous,
1990, p11).
Object Alternation
Test (OAT): This is a test first devised for use with animals (e.g., Pribram and
Mishkin, 1956) and then adapted for use with humans (Freedman, 1990). It requires
the integration of short-term visual memory and simple rule learning. The
patient is seated in front of two black "plaques", either, both, or
neither of which can be used to cover over a small object such as a coin. The
patient thus has to learn the rule, but can perseverate with said rule
once it has been established. The perseveration score may be abbreviated to
OAT-PE. Poor performance on the OAT is usually associated with lesions of
orbitofrontal cortex (Freedman, 1990).
Object-Awareness: [Or "o-awareness", for short.] This is one
of the three subtypes of awareness suggested by Dretske (e.g., 1997) [the
others being fact awareness and property awareness]. For further
details, see consciousness, Dretske's
theory of.
Object, Bad:
[See firstly object (2).] This is
Klein's (e.g., 1935) basic notion of any object from the outside world which,
by failing to satisfy one of an infant's basic impulses fully enough or quickly
enough becomes more or less instantly an instrument of frustration rather than
an instrument of satisfaction. Here is Klein herself on both the phenomenon and
its underlying psychodynamic mechanisms .....
"The development of the infant is governed by the
mechanisms of introjection and projection. From the beginning the ego
introjects objects 'good' and 'bad', for both of which its mother's breast is
the prototype - for good objects when the child obtains it and for bad when it
fails him. But it is because the baby projects its own aggression on to these
objects that it feels them to be 'bad' and not only in that they frustrate its
desires: the child conceives of them as actually dangerous - persecutors who it
fears will devour it [etc.] Hence quite little children pass through anxiety
situations (and react to them with defense
mechanisms), the content of which is comparable to that of the psychoses of
adults" (Klein, 1935/1986), pp116-117).
As the infant grows older, conflicts between good and
bad objects go on to shape its emerging personality, not least by creating various
habitual recourses to different defense mechanisms - denial, expulsion, and
projection, being especially important. Klein suggests, for example, that manic
states are based on a misuse of the mechanism of denial, and characterised by a
"sense of omnipotence" (p133) developed to control bad objects.
Marginally more pathological sequences of psychodynamic events underlie the
schizoid defenses. Here is Klein (1946/1986) on the topic of "schizoid
object relations" .....
"To summarise now some of the disturbed object
relations which are found in schizoid personalities: the violent splitting of
the self and excessive projection have the effect that the person towards whom
this process is directed is felt as a persecutor. Since the destructive and
hated part of the self which is split off and projected is felt as a danger to
the loved object and therefore gives rise to guilt, this process of projection
in some ways also implies a deflection of guilt from the self on to the other
person. Guilt has, however, not been done away with, and the deflected guilt is
felt as an unconscious responsibility for the people who have become
representatives of the aggressive part of the self. Another typical feature of
schizoid object relations is their narcissistic nature which derives from the
infantile introjective and projective processes. For, as I suggested earlier,
when the ego ideal is projected into another person, this person becomes
predominantly loved and admired because he contains the good parts of the self.
Similarly, the relation to another person on the basis of projecting bad parts
of the self into him is of a narcissistic nature, because in this case as well
the object strongly represents one part of the self. Both these types of
narcissistic relation to an object often show strong obsessional features. The impulse to control other people is, as
we know, an essential element in obsessional neurosis
[and] can to some extent be explained by a deflected drive to control parts of
the self. When these parts have been projected
excessively into another person, they can only be controlled by controlling the
other person. One
root of obsessional mechanisms may thus be found in the particular
identification which results from infantile projective processes" (Klein,
1946/1986, p187; emphasis added).
Armstrong-Perlman (1994) reminds us that bad objects
persist into adult life, where they serve to predispose people towards
corrosive and unsuccessful relationships. Thus .....
"With these patients, one often finds a history
of detachment or even active rejection of others in their erotic relationships.
Such people are often significantly high achievers [but] as resources for
others. [.....] The currently lost, or about to be lost, others have been
objects of desire for these patients. The patients have felt 'real' in these
relationships. Yet when they give a history of their relationships, one wonders
at their blindness. Their object choices seem pathological or perverse. There are indications that the others were
or are incapable of reciprocating, or loving, or accepting the patients in the
way they desire. The patients have been
pursuing alluring but rejecting objects - exciting yet frustrating objects" (Armstrong-Perlman, 1994, p223).
Object Concept:
[See firstly object and concept.] In the context of the present
glossary, we usually see the term "object concept" as the English
rendering of Freud's (1891/1953) Objektvorstellung.
The theoretical status of both the words and the underlying
notion have been discussed by Rizzuto (1990), and the caution raised
that the classical Greek problems with forms still troubled Northern
European philosophy late in the 19th century. Cassirer (1929/1957) puts his
finger perfectly on the problem, thus .....
"The question of the object has become for Kant a
question of validity, of the quid juris
[= that which is currently being decided]; but the quid juris of the object cannot be decided before the other
question, the quid juris of the
concept, has been answered. For the
concept is the last and highest stage to which knowledge rises in the progress
of the objective consciousness. In the building up of objective knowledge
the synthesis of 'apprehension in intuition' and of 'reproduction in the
imagination' must be completed by the synthesis of 'recognition in the
concept'. To recognise an object means nothing other than to subject the
manifold of intuition to a rule which determines it in respect to its order.
And the concept is nothing other than the consciousness of such a rule and of
the unity that is posited through it" (Cassirer, 1929/2957, p315; emphasis
added).
Rizzuto (1990) adds .....
"Philosophically, Freud adheres to the teachings
of John Stuart Mill that the object representation does not contain anything
else besides the appearance of a 'thing'. [.....] By talking about the
appearance of a 'thing', Freud and Mill make a clear distinction between a
'thing' (Ding), a material object, existing in the real world,
and its representation, the 'appearance' of an object in the mind. This Objektvorstellung
is constructed in the process of perceiving and belongs entirely to the psychic
realm. A 'thing' can be there, in front of the viewer as a Gegenstand
[.....]. Another way of saying the same in German is Objekt
[.....]. For Kant an Objekt is a human construction made out of
sensations originating in and referred to an existing thing in factual reality.
An object representation is therefore a psychic representation that
resembles a 'thing' that is there in the world" (p242).
Object
Constancy (1/2): There are two
distinct usages of this term in cognitive science, as follows: (1) In perceptual theory, an "object constancy" is the
name commonly given to the visual system's capacity to make due allowances for
the changes in retinal angles subtended as objects of factually fixed
dimensions move away from or towards the eyes. (2) In psychodynamic theory,
on the other hand, an "object constancy" is
the term used by object relations
theorists to describe the enduring
quality of particular psychodynamic objects during longitudinal psychosexual
development.
Object
Fusion: In the context of the present
glossary, this is Jacobson's (1964) notion of a process whereby self and object
images become effectively one and the same at a particular point in cognitive
and psychosexual development. Here is the core proposal
.....
"I have repeatedly stated that at first the
infant can probably hardly discriminate between his own pleasurable sensations
and the objects from which they are derived. Only when the perceptive functions
have sufficiently matured can gratifications or frustrations become associated
with the object. [.....] Induced by such repeated unpleasurable experiences of
frustration and separation from the love object, fantasies of (total)
incorporation of the gratifying object begin to arise, expressive of wishes to
re-establish the lost unit. This desire probably never ceases to play a part in
our emotional life. [.....] These earliest wishful fantasies of merging and
being one with the mother (breast) are certainly the foundation on which all
object relations as well as all future types of identification are built"
(Jacobson, 1964, p39).
Object-Oriented
DBMS: This
is a database created using a DBMS built according to the
principles of object-oriented computing.
Object-Oriented
Computing:
[See firstly object (3).] This is a strategy for maximising the
efficiency of computer code by concentrating at all design stages, (but
especially that of data analysis and database design) on the content
to be processed rather than the act of processing it [compare the act vs
content debate in mental philosophy]. Khoshafian
and Abnous (1990) introduce this issue as follows .....
"Using conventional techniques, the code
generated for a real-world problem consists of first encoding the problem and
then transforming the problem into terms of a von Neumann computer language. Object-oriented
disciplines and techniques handle the transformation automatically, so the bulk
of the code just encodes the problem and the transformation is minimised. In
fact, when compared to more conventional (procedural) styles of programming,
code reductions ranging from 40% to an order of magnitude have been reported.
[Therefore] the object-oriented concepts and tools are enabling technologies
that allow real-world problems to be expressed easily and naturally [and]
provide better methodologies to construct complex software systems out of
modularised reusable software units." (Khoshafian and Abnous, 1990, pp7-8)
Within the computer world, the ideal object is an
"encapsulated" (= physically delineated) sequence of machine code within what is otherwise a
conventional program, which has been deliberately set up as such by an
object-oriented compiler from an equally encapsulated run of source code. The
result is a machine instantiation of a real world object, and the fact that it
remains encapsulated at machine code level gives it a powerful practical appeal
as a means of delivering "re-usable software". Indeed, object
orientation "can be loosely described as the software modelling and
development (engineering) disciplines that make it easy to construct complex
systems from individual components" (Khoshafian and Abnous, 1990, p6;
italics original).
Object
Permanence: In Piagetian theory, this
is the belief, emerging at around age 8-9 months, that
objects continue to exist even when they have moved out of sight.
Object
Relations Theory: [See firstly object (2).] Object Relations Theory is a derivative of conventional psychodynamic
theory which evolved around the middle of the 20th century at the hands of the
post-Freudian Melanie Klein, and which was then further developed by the likes
of William Fairbairn, Donald Winnicott, Margaret Mahler, Edith Jacobsen, and
Otto Kernberg. The defining emphasis of this brand of psychodynamic
theory is its emphasis on the knowledge structures of the developing mind, and
how well they integrate (a) the infant's growing knowledge of the outside world
- perforce its experiences with its primary caregiver(s) - with (b) the
emotional forces driving psychosexual development. Object relations theory is
thus especially powerful when directed at "the emergence of the preoedipal
child from the mother-infant field" (Spruiell, 1977/2006 online). Klee (2001
online) [homepage]
once rather vividly put it this way .....
"Early in life, we have
little sense of ourselves, or our identity. It is through our relationships
with the significant people around us that we take in parts of others (objects)
and slowly build a self-structure, which we eventually call a personality. This
blueprint of a self-structure is formed early in life out of our relationships
with the objects (significant others, and parts of significant others) around
us. Once formed, the blueprint can be modified, but our basic tendency is to
seek out others (friends, spouses) who will reaffirm those early self-object
relationships. It is as if in early childhood we create a script for a drama
and then spend the rest of our lives seeking out others to play the parts"
Bollas (1987) reminds us of
the contribution of another early Kleinian, Paula Heimann .....
"In the early 1950s
Paula Heimann [.....] posed a simple question that
became crucial to [.....] the 'British School' of psychoanalysis. When
listening to the patient's free associations (or broken speech), and tracing
the private logic of sequential association [.....] she asked: 'Who is
speaking?' We can say that up until this moment it had always been assumed that
the speaker was the patient who had formed a therapeutic alliance with the
analyst, and therefore that he was a neutral or working speaker who was
reporting inner states of mind. This assumption comprised the classical view of
analytic narrative. But Heimann knew that at any one moment in a session a
patient could be speaking with the voice of the mother, or the mood of the
father, or some fragmented voice of a child self either lived or withheld from
life. 'To whom is this person speaking?' Heimann then asked. The
unconscious admits no special recognition of the neutrality of the
psychoanalyst and, given the unending subtleties of the transference, Heimann
realised that at one moment the analysand was speaking to the mother,
anticipating the father, or reproaching, exciting, or consoling a child - the
child self of infancy, in the midst of separation at age two, in the oedipal
phase, or in adolescence" (Bollas, 1987, p1; emphasis added).
Daniels (2007 online)
offers a useful web resource on the leading workers in this field and their
basic terminology, and Kernberg (1967) shows how the theory can be used to
excellent effect in helping us to understand borderline personality disorder.
See also the sequence of infant cognitive development proposed by Ryle (1991)
in the entry for procedural sequence model.
Object
Representation: See object concept.
Object, Self as: [See
firstly object relations theory.]
The idea that the self is an object (2)
built up from other objects is basic to all variants of Kleinian theory. Here
is how one modern object relations theorist traces the notion back to one of
the pioneers of the genre .....
"In living with borderline, schizoid, and
narcissistic character disorders, Winnicott knew that he was immersed in the
patient's unconscious reconstruction of a child's environment, and I understand
that it was a feature of his technique to adapt himself to the patient's ego
defects and characterological biases in order to allow for the transference to
evolve without the impingement of a premature use of analytic interpretation.
From this experiencing of the early infant environment, the analyst could then
interpret the past as it was re-created through the transference. People bear
memories of being the mother's and father's object in ego structure, and in the
course of a person's object relations he re-presents various positions in the
historical theatre of lived experiences between elements of mother, father, and
his infant-child self. One idiom of representation is the person's relation to
the self as an object, an object relation where the individual may objectify,
imagine, analyse, and manage the self through identification with primary
others who have been involved in that very task. I find the concept of the
relation to the self as an object to be of considerable use to me in my
clinical work [..... but] do not think it has been adequately
conceptualised" (Bollas, 1987, p41).
[See now object,
transformational for more on Bollas' particular approach to object relations, or projective
identification for more on the Kleinian view in general.
Object,
Transformational: [See firstly object relations theory.] This is Bollas'
(1987) notion of a mental object in the Kleinian psychodynamic sense [see object, self as] which - deriving as it
does from the primary caregiver - is centrally involved in the emergence of the
very earliest ego structures in a growing infant.
ASIDE: By reminding us of the "considerable prematurity
of human birth" (p13), Bollas is effectively blaming evolution for much of
human mental illness. In species whose young "leave the nest" early
in life, the parents have less opportunity to shape not just their growing
bodies but their minds as well. By the same token, however, they also have less
opportunity to pervert that growth process by inflicting their own inadequacies
upon them, or trans-generationally re-infecting them with their own perversions.
To use a slightly more recent phrase, they have less opportunity to become toxic parents.
Bollas (1987) begins by delving back through
developmental time to "the infant's first subjective experience of the
object as a transformational object" (p14), as now explained
.....
"A transformational object is experientially
identified by the infant with processes that alter self experience. It is an
identification that emerges from symbiotic relating, where the first object is
'known' not so much by putting it into an object representation, but as a
recurrent experience of being - a more existential as opposed to
representational knowing. As the mother helps to integrate the infant's being
(instinctual, cognitive, affective, environmental),
the rhythms of this process - from unintegration(s) to integration(s) - inform
the nature of this 'object' relation rather than the qualities of the object as
object. Not yet fully identified as an
other, the mother is experienced as a process of transformation,
and this feature of early existence lives on in certain forms of object-seeking
in adult life, when the object is sought for its function as a signifier of
transformation. Thus, in adult life, the quest is not to possess the
object; rather the object is pursued in order to surrender to it as a medium
that alters the self [.....] Since it is an identification that begins before
the mother is mentally represented as an other, it is
an object relation that emerges not from desire, but from a perceptual
identification of the object with its function: the object as enviro-somatic
transformer of the subject. The memory of this early object
relation manifests itself in the person's search for an object (a person,
place, event, ideology) that promises to transform the self" (Bollas,
1987, p14; emphasis added).
In other words, Bollas sees the mother as constantly
altering the infant's experience, without
being able to experience that experience for herself (at least neither from
the infant's perspective, nor in the infant's very restricted terms). All too
often, by accident or malicious intent, the mother simply fails to provide
"the facilitating environment" [compare holding environment] necessary to build the infant's ego.
RESEARCH
ISSUE: So what
forces are at work, then, and in what causal sequence, when the mother is
herself less than cognitively adequate? Might it be possible, for example, that
something as seemingly innocent as one of the intelligence s-factors, perhaps,
might be a key variable here, capable of subtly impoverishing the mother's
intellectual input into her child's development? Or that one of the cognitive deficits recognised in the special educational needs arena is
capable of damaging not just the parent's job and academic prospects but their
ability as parents too [readers unfamiliar with the cognitive deficits approach
may care to read up on the feedback
theory of schizophrenia [see
Frith (1979)], the order of
representation theory of autism
[see meta-representation], the phonological memory theory of dyslexia [see companion resource,
Section 4.4], or the defective functional connectivity theory of toxic parenting and other forms of special educational needs. Might we, in
other words, have a potential cognitive
deficit explanation of something as psychosexually charged as personality
disorder? Even more specifically, might
object relations failures in psychodynamic terms be object relations failures
also in computational terms?
Bollas goes on to argue that much of our later adult
life is spent searching out substitutes for the transformational object, and
that the person who then enters psychoanalysis will automatically require the
analyst "to experience the patient's inner object world" (p5). This
can only be done effectively, he argues, using the process of projective identification [for Bollas'
argument here, see that entry]. [See now unthought known.]
Objective
(Various Meanings): [CAUTION:
In the awkward squad of philosophical terms - words which have been used with
so many nuances of meaning over the years that they can obscure rather than
clarify the point at hand - the word "objective" is one of the very
awkwardest. Use it carefully yourself, therefore, and check that those whose
words you may be following have done likewise.] In everyday English, the word
"objective" can function either as an adjective ("to be objective";
"to value objective evidence") or as a noun ("to set an objective").
The following variations in usage are presented under their original O.E.D. numbering .....
"(2) Philos.
Used of the esistence or nature of a thing as
an object of consciousness (as distinguished from an existence or nature
termed subjective. [..... (3)] Dealing with, or laying stress upon, that
which is external to the mind; treating of outward things or events, rather
than inward thoughts or feelings [..... (4)] That is the object of sensation or
thought; that is presented or exposed as an object, perceived, apprehended,
etc. [.....] (8) Orig. Mil., the point towards which
the advance of troops is directed; hence gen. the point aimed at"
(O.E.D.).
But as if those complexities were not enough, the word
is also commonly encountered in mental philosophy as a straight Anglicisation
of the German philosophical term Objektive
[pronounce as "ob - yect - Eva"], itself marvellously difficult to
pin down [see the entry following]. And worse, because in optics, "the
objective" is the outermost lens in a series of lenses (that is to say,
the one which actually first receives the light from the object [see explanatory diagram
(courtesy of Wikipedia)]), which is
precisely the role which the eye plays in the end-to-end process of aesthesis.
Objective
Anxiety: See anxiety types.
Objective
Idealism: See Idealism, Objective.
Objektiv: [Pl.
Objektive.] [German = "objective".] We are concerned in this
glossary only with Meinong's (1902/1983)
technical usage of this term, which was to name a brief but vitally important
(and nearly as poorly understood now as then) transitional stage of perception,
during which a particular "object of judgment" was delineated
which might not totally equate to the literal contents of the sensory field
[for an example and further discussion, see the entry for consciousness,
Meinong's theory of]. Meinong's theory of aesthesis has recently been
revisited by Sierszulska (2005), who phrases the key assertion as follows .....
"Since objectives are the proper objects intended
in acts of judgment and assumption, they are called objects as well, even
though they are neither real existing objects, nor do they belong to the
general category of objecta" (p40).
See Jacquette (2007 online) for the current
state of play.
Objektvorstellung: [German Objekt = "object" + Vorstellung
= "concept".] See object
concept.
Obsession: In
the context of the present glossary, obsessions are "persistent ideas,
thoughts, impulses, or images, that are experienced as intrusive and
inappropriate and that cause marked anxiety or distress" (DSM-IV, 2000,
p437).
Obsessional Neurosis: This is Freud's (1896) notion of a neurosis characterised by clinically
significant levels of uncontrolled cognitive content, capable of distorting the
behaviour of the patient in question in one or more key areas. The nature of
the cognitive content is repetitive and prescriptive - hence the allusion to
"obsession" - and the nature of the resulting behavioural distortions
is that they are as hauntingly persistent as they are bizarre or idiosyncratic.
One of Freud's earliest mentions of obsessional characteristics is in Freud and
Breuer (1893-1895), and he returned to the subject in one of his letters to his
friend Wilhelm Fliess, as follows .....
"With regard to obsessional neurosis, I have
found confirmation that the locality at which the repressed breaks through is
the word presentation and not the
concept attached to it. (More precisely, the word memory.)
Hence the most disparate things are readily united as an obsessional idea under
a single word with multiple meanings. [.....] Obsessional ideas frequently are
clothed in a characteristic verbal
vagueness [see sidenote below - Ed.] in order to permit [.....] multiple
deployment" (Freud, letter of 22nd December 1897, Letters to Fliess [Masson (1985), pp287-288]).
ASIDE: Note the observation concerning "verbal vagueness"
above, and then compare the notion of "overinclusive thinking" in
psychotic patients [start with the entry for cognitive deficit,
and then move on to the entry for theory
of mind theory of schizophrenia].
Freud's ideas were then presented in greater detail in
case, Rat Man (Freud, 1909) [see the separate entry for the gory
details], and then summarised as follows in his Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis .....
"Obsessional neurosis [Zwangsneurose] and
hysteria are the forms of neurotic illness upon the study of which
psychoanalysis was first built [.....]. But obsessional neurosis, in which the
puzzling leap from the mental to the physical plays no part, has actually,
through the efforts of psychoanalysis, become more perspicuous and familiar to
us than hysteria, and we have learned that it displays certain extreme
characteristics of the nature of neuroses far more glaringly. Obsessional neurosis is shown in the patient's being occupied with thoughts in
which he is in fact not interested, in his being aware of impulses in
himself which appear very strange to him, and in his
being led to actions the performance of which give him no enjoyment, but
which it is quite impossible for him to omit. The thoughts (obsessions) may be senseless in themselves, or merely a
matter of indifference to the subject; often they are completely silly, and
invariably they are the starting-point of a strenuous mental activity, which
exhausts the patient and to which he only surrenders himself most unwillingly"
(Freud, Introductory Lectures,
1917/1963, p297; bold emphasis added).
For her part, Melanie Klein saw obsessions as closely related to omnipotence and the "bad" object. WHERE TO NEXT: A number of illustrative clinical cases have been
described over the years, for example, case,
obsessional (aged 30 years) and case,
obsessional (aged 19 years). Obsessional neuroses have been incorporated
into the modern psychiatric lexicon under the headings obsessive-compulsive disorder and obsessive-compulsive personality disorder.
Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder: [CAUTION - compare obsessive-compulsive personality disorder.] This is one of the
thirteen DSM-IV disorder groups
under the category header of anxiety
disorders. It is characterised by "recurrent obsessions or compulsions
[] that are serious enough to be time consuming (i.e., they take more than 1
hour a day) or cause marked distress or significant impairment" (DSM-IV,
2000, pp456-457).
Obsessive-Compulsive Personality Disorder: [CAUTION - compare obsessive-compulsive disorder.] This is one of the eleven DSM-IV disorder groups under the
category header of personality disorders.
Occam: See Ockham.
Occurrentness: See Dreyfus, Hubert L.
OCEAN: See personality
factors, "Big Five" system of.
Ockham, William of: [British monk-philosopher
(1285?-1349?) (a.k.a. Doctor Invincibilis).] [Click for external
biography] William of Ockham (sometimes Occam) was a fourteenth century
English philosopher, who developed what has since been described as the
"rule of ontogenetical economy" (Magnusson, 1990, p1096).
"Entities," he wrote, "are not to be multiplied beyond
necessity". In other words, when you are faced with explaining the
unexplained, the simplest explanations are usually the best.
Oedipus, The Tyrant: <Οιδιπους
Τιραννος>
O Zeus, what hast thou willed to do with me! (Oedipus, upon realising his double
transgression).
Where are you, children? Come, feel your brother's
hands. (Oedipus, to
his sister-daughters).
In this Greek tragedy by Sophocles (ca. 428 BCE), the
plot revolves around the revelation to King Oedipus of Thebes that he was not
as "true a son of his sire" as he had originally believed himself to
be. The man Oedipus called "father" - King Polybus of Corinth [a
nearby rival state - see
map] - was in fact only his adoptive father, having acquired him as
an infant-foundling, and having raised him as his own. In fact, Oedipus was the
long-lost son of King Laius and Queen Jocasta of Thebes, and the crucial plot
twist is that his birth had not been welcomed in the royal palace because Laius
had previously been warned by a fortune-teller - an "oracle" - that
he would one day perish at the hands of his own son. Laius had accordingly
ordered the new-born child put to death by the then-traditional method of
exposure upon a hillside, but had been betrayed by the squeamishness of the
servant entrusted with this grisliest of tasks.
ASIDE: The manuscript is infuriatingly confused as to what
exactly had happened. Laius seems to have personally passed a pin-shackle
through the baby's ankles to bind them together [the name Oedipus derives from
the "swollen feet" this abuse inflicted upon the infant], and the
appointed servant - a royal herdsman - seems at first to have abandoned the
child as instructed, only for it to be discovered while still alive by a passing
shepherd. A character referred to in the play as "the messenger"
(coincidentally, also a shepherd) explains to Oedipus that he got the child
from "a herdsman of the king". As with all dark secrets, however,
this explanation shifts from one telling to the next [check out the Storr translation text,
courtesy of the Internet Classics Archive
at MIT]. What does seem agreed is that one or other of the intermediaries had
given the baby to Polybus, "a childless man 'til then", as "a
gift" (e43). The text is also never entirely clear as to whether Jocasta
was party to the abandonment or was told about it after it had happened.
Oedipus duly grew safely to manhood, and all was well
[but see Research Issue below]. Then one day he himself consulted an
oracle, only to hear it foretold that he would "mate with his own mother
and kill his own father". Not overly impressed with either of these ideas,
he resolved to distance himself from his "parents", and so set off to
seek his fortune elsewhere. On this journey, he ran [as you do] straight into
his biological father, Laius. As strangers (but clearly from the same
quarrelsome gene-pool), they disagreed over who had right of way at a certain
crossroads and in the ensuing fracas Oedipus killed the older man [one up to
the oracle]. He then made his way to Thebes [now kingless, remember] where he
was able (by outwitting a mythical monster) to win both the vacant throne and -
with it - the hand of the widow Queen [his mother, remember [and not just the
hand, needless to say, for by his "begetting where he was begot" she
would bear him four children]]. An accumulation of events then gradually
reveals all these hidden truths to him, and in the bloody denouement [in which,
even as a non-clinician, we suspect we see the forces of narcissistic self revenge at work] Jocasta commits suicide and
Oedipus puts out his own eyes and is banished from the kingdom.
RESEARCH ISSUE: Oedipus has long been acclaimed as a
study in scarring more substantial than those upon his ankles. Jocasta herself
relates (e-version, p30) that her child had been "but three days old"
when her husband had given him "to be cast away by others on the trackless
mountainside". We therefore need to enquire what sort of upbringing the
child went through at the hands of Polybus (the adoptive father) and Merope
(the adoptive mother) to have turned him into the personality he gradually
shows himself to be. What we know, or may strongly suspect, about his genetic parents
[Laius and Jocasta] is that the father was a quick-tempered superstitious
homosexual rapist, drunkard, and child-abuser, and the mother was quite
possibly the sort of woman who submits to, rather than stands up to, the
tempers of infanticidal husband (and with suicidal tendencies into the
bargain). What we know about the adoptive
parents [Polybus and Merope] is that they were probably incapable of having
children of their own and kept the fact of the adoption from the child himself.
The selected header quotation also surely indicates an unhealthy degree of
"externality" in Oedipus's locus of control, in that he blames
the Gods for what is probably a simple demonstration of the power of nature
over nurture.
[See now Oedipus
complex. A number of cognate myths are discussed in the entry for national heroes, psychodynamic theory and.]
Oiesis: [Greek <οιησις>
= "opinion" (O.C.G.D.), but
in some senses also "human mind".] As we noted in the G2 entry
for aesthesis, phenomenal awareness, and
ideation, Plato used the word oiesis
rather experimentally on occasions, it being a derivative of oida, "I know", and thus a
close relative of ειδος. Here
are two specimen extracts, the second of which renders the word, in
translation, as "human mind" .....
“SOCRATES: [….. Oiesis] seems to express the fact that
thinking is the motion (oisis) of the
soul towards every thing, toward how each of the things that are really is”
(Plato, Cratylus, §420c; Reeve
translation, p63).
"..... because it gives the human mind [oiesis] insight [nous]
and information [historia] in a
rational way ....." (Plato, Phaedrus, §244c; Waterfield translation, p26).
Omnipotence: This is one of the defense mechanisms postulated by psychoanalytic theory, and
recognised by the DSM-IV as
belonging to the "minor image-distorting" defense level. It involves dealing with emotional conflict "by
feeling or acting as if [one] possesses special powers or abilities and is
superior to others" (DSM-IV, 2000, p812). The term comes from Melanie
Klein, thus .....
"As has already been stated, omnipotence prevails
in the early phantasies, both the destructive and the reparative ones, and
influences sublimations as well as object relations. Omnipotence, however, is
so closely bound up in the unconscious with the sadistic impulses with which it
was first associated that the child feels again and again that his attempts at
reparation have not succeeded, or will not succeed. His sadistic impulses, he
feels, may easily get the better of him. The young child, who cannot
sufficiently trust his reparative and constructive feelings, as we have seen,
resorts to manic omnipotence. [.....]
All this leads to the need in the child - and for that
matter to some extent in the adult also - to repeat certain actions
obsessionally (this, in my view, is part of the repetition compulsion); or -
the contrasting method - omnipotence and denial are resorted to" (Klein,
1940/1986, pp152-153).
One-To-Many Relationship: See relationship,
one-to-many.
One-To-One Relationship: See relationship,
one-to-one.
On[ta]:
[Greek = "being(s)".] The word on
was used in the discussion of reality and appearance in Plato's The Sophist
(§244a; Cornford translation, p219). Plato's on is the present
participle [the "I am X-ing" form of the standard
English verb] of the irregular Greek verb einai, "to be". Cornford (1935) translates this as "the
real" or "reality" (p216, footnote) rather than the more
straightforward "being", whilst Heidegger rendered it as Seiende for the German marketplace.
Ontic: [See firstly on[ta].] Concerning the ultimate nature
of reality. [See, for example, ontic distinctiveness.]
Ontic
Distinctiveness: [See firstly ontology.] This is Strawson's (1997)
term for a fundamentally different class of reality. He applies it specifically
to the issue of whether a self is "an 'ontically distinct' thing"
(p425).
Ontology: [See firstly onta.]
"The science or study of being; that department of metaphysics which relates to the being
or essence of things, or to being in the abstract" (O.E.D.).
Heidegger (1927) puts it this way .....
"The task of ontology is to explain Being itself and to make the Being of entities stand out in
full relief" (Being and Time, p49).
Operating
System: The key to understanding what an operating system is lies in grasping a
single basic fact, namely that a high proportion of one's computer software
re-uses code already written (often at great cost) elsewhere. It therefore makes
sense not just to provide the applications programmers with a library of tried
and tested subroutines, but also with a way of accessing these procedures from
within a programmer-friendly keying environment. The operating system is the
mechanism by which this is all achieved, and its standard functions include
interfacing with the operator, managing the library procedures, managing the
peripherals, displaying the contents of magnetic media, knowing what filenames
have been allocated, knowing where on the available disks it has put each file
(and the really clever operating systems are able to store a given file in a
number of non-contiguous fragments, so that takes a lot of managing), managing
disk I-O, issuing warnings, help, and error messages, keeping track of date and
time, and marking same on the filestock so users know how old they are, and
last (but by no means least) controlling the execution of end-user programs.
Some operating systems are easier to get along with than others. The worst ones
are those invented in the days before the general public were
allowed to get their hands on computers. The easy to use ones are called
"user friendly", and the trend of late has been for them to become
more and more user friendly as time goes by. Operating systems are
written by "boffins" and maintained by "systems
programmers", who (because they are the only ones who understand what they
are doing) get paid a lot more than applications programmers. For the view that biological consciousness serves in
some way as the mind's operating system, see consciousness, Johnson-Laird's
theory of. [See also virtual machine and virtual machine operating system.]
Operation: This is Piagetian theory's
term for the basic unit of thinking. Here is how this construct is explained in
Piaget (1970) .....
"First of all, an
operation is an action that can be internalised; that is, it can be carried out
in thought as well as executed materially. Second, it is a reversible action;
that is, it can take place in one direction or in the opposite direction. This
is not true of all actions. If I smoke my pipe through to the end, I cannot
reverse this action [.....] The third characteristic of an operation is that it
always supposes some conservation, some invariant. It is of course a
transformation, since it is an action, but it is a transformation that does not
transform everything at once [.....] The fourth characteristic is that no
operation exists alone. Every operation is related to a system of operations,
or to a total structure as we call it [.....] a system governed by laws that
apply to the system as such, and not only to one or another element in the
system" (Genetic Epistemology,
pp21-22).
Opinion: [See firstly doxa.] In everyday usage,
an opinion is "what one thinks or how one thinks about something"
(O.E.D.). Within mental philosophy it becomes an important, but vaguely
defined, aspect of thinking, one weapon among many in the mind's armoury of higher
cognitive functions. Plato offers the following insight in the Cratylus
dialogue .....
"HERMOGENES: What do
you think of doxa ('opinion'), and the like? SOCRATES: Doxa ('opinion') either
derives from the pursuit (dioxis) the soul engages in when it hunts for
the knowledge of how things are, or it derives from the shooting of a bow (toxon).
But the latter is more likely. At any rate, 'oiesis' ('thinking') is in
harmony with it. It seems to express the fact that thinking is the motion (oisis)
of the soul towards every thing, towards how each of the things that are really
is" (Plato, Cratylus, §420b;
Reeve translation, p63).
Oppositional Defiant Disorder: This is one of the five DSM-IV disorder groups under the category header of attention-deficit and disruptive behaviour
disorders. It presents as "an enduring pattern of uncooperative,
defiant, and hostile behaviour toward authority figures" (PsychNet-UK),
far beyond that normally seen in children and adolescents. You also need to
exclude the possibility of a cognitive
deficit of the sort described in the entry for Asperger's disorder, where the oppositional defiance - troubling
enough though it is - is tangential to the real problem.
Ordinary State of Consciousness (OSC): This is one of the two basic states of consciousness identified by Harner (1980) (the other
being the Shamanic state of
consciousness).
Organelle: A subcellular
structure (or class of structures), such as the Golgi apparatus, the mitochondria,
or the ribosomes.
Organoleptic:
From the evidence of the senses.
Orienting: Maintaining
general everyday awareness. One of the first things to be established in the Routine
Neurological Examination is "orientation to time, person, and
place". This involves asking such questions as "Do you know where you
are, Ethel?", "Can you tell me who the Prime Minister is?", and so on. Orienting can therefore be regarded as
one of the all-pervading components of intact and effective executive
function, because it helps establish attention in the first instance, and
thereafter makes both planning and execution-monitoring more appropriate.
Originär /
Originarität: [German =
"primordial / primordiality".] See consciousness, Husserl's theory of.
Orthodromic
Conduction: The propagation of a neural impulse in the "forwards" direction,
that is to say, from a point of stimulation on the axon away from the cell
body. The opposite of antidromic conduction.
OSC: See ordinary state of consciousness.
OSI Reference Model: The Open Systems Interconnection
(OSI) Reference Model is a set of standards developed by the
telecommunications industry during the 1970s and set down formally in Zimmerman
(1980). It is a reasonably non-technical overriding guideline, and it
recommends a seven-layered analysis for any given communication, with the
physical channel (the wire, etc.) consigned to the lowest level, and each layer
communicating logically (but not physically) with the matching decoding
layer(s) at other node(s). This type of arrangement is known as
"peer-to-peer communication" (Gandoff, 1990). The OSI model thus
allows information to pass smoothly and progressively down the seven layers of
the sending processing hierarchy and just as effortlessly up the seven layers
of the receiving processing hierarchy, managing the entire process, and
supporting appropriate error detection and recovery processes should
difficulties arise. [If interested in the role played by error detection and
recovery processes in real time biological control processes, see our comments
on "awareness of awareness" in the entry for Central State Materialism. If interested in the detail of the
process, see Section 3 of our e-resource on
"Shannonian Theory".]
Ousia: [Greek = "being, essence, substance;
property" (O.C.G.D.); "substance, existence" (Peters).] This is
one of the most important words in classical philosophy because it is not just
the first of Aristotle's ten categories
and the key to Plato's true being,
but it is also the key to Heidegger's notion of Dasein and the effective
development of computerised propositional
networks! Consider .....
"The noun
ουσια is derived from one of the stems used in
conjugating the irregular verb ειναι ('to be'); in the
Aristotelian tradition it is usually translated as 'substance', though
translators of Plato are more likely to write 'essence', 'existence' or
'being'. Heidegger suggests that ουσια is to be
thought of as synonymous with the derivative noun παρουσια
('being-at', 'presence')" (Macquarrie and Robinson, 1962, p47 footnote to
Heidegger, 1927/1962).
"'Ousia' is a verbal noun from the Greek verb 'to
be'. As Aristotle uses the word, it occurs in two distinct grammatical constructions.
We can say that x is an ousia - a being, reality, or substance; or we can say
that the ousia of x is F, where 'F' answers the 'What is it?' question about x.
[.....] On the first use, ousiai are the basic beings there are, whatever these
turn out to be. To call something an ousia, in this sense, is to confer
basicness [..... as a] primary substance. [.....] In its second use,
Aristotle often identifies a thing's ousia with its essence or nature [e.g.]; so let us call this sort of ousia: essence"
(Fine, 2003, pp398-399).
[See
now data analysis, Dasein,
artificial, and entity-relationship diagram.]
Outrider: The Outrider is/was one of the "troops",
the alter personalities in case, Truddi Chase.
Overinclusive Thinking: See cognitive deficit.
See the
Master References List
[Up]
[Home]